Mathematics of apportionment explained

In mathematics and social choice, apportionment problems are a class of fair division problems where the goal is to divide (apportion) a whole number of identical goods fairly between multiple groups with different entitlements. The original example of an apportionment problem involves distributing seats in a legislature between different federal states or political parties.[1] However, apportionment methods can be applied to other situations as well, including bankruptcy problems,[2] inheritance law (e.g. dividing animals),[3] [4] manpower planning (e.g. demographic quotas),[5] and rounding percentages.[6]

Mathematically, an apportionment method is just a method of rounding real numbers to integers. Despite the simplicity of this problem, every method of rounding suffers one or more paradoxes, as proven by the Balinski-Young theorem. The mathematical theory of apportionment identifies what properties can be expected from an apportionment method.

The mathematical theory of apportionment was studied as early as 1907 by the mathematician Agner Krarup Erlang. It was later developed to a great detail by the mathematician Michel Balinski and the economist Peyton Young.[7]

Definitions

Input

The inputs to an apportionment method are:

h

representing the total number of items to allocate. It is also called the house size, since in many cases, the items to allocate are seats in a house of representatives.

n

representing the number of agents to which items should be allocated. For example, these can be federal states or political parties.

(t1,\ldots,tn)

representing entitlements -

ti

represents the entitlement of agent

i

, that is, the amount of items to which

i

is entitled (out of the total of

h

). These entitlements are often normalized such that
n
\sum
i=1

ti=1

. Alternatively, they can be normalized such that their sum is

h

; in this case the entitlements are called quotas and termed denoted by

qi

, where

qi:=tih

and
n
\sum
i=1

qi=h

. Alternatively, one is given a vector of populations

(p1,\ldots,pn)

; here, the entitlement of agent

i

is

ti=pi/

n
\sum
j=1

pj

.

Output

The output is a vector of integers

a1,\ldots,an

with
n
\sum
i=1

ai=h

, called an apportionment of

h

, where

ai

is the number of items allocated to agent i.

For each agent

i

, the real number

qi:=tih

is called the quota of

i

, and denotes the exact number of items that should be given to

i

. In general, a "fair" apportionment is one in which each allocation

ai

is as close as possible to the quota

qi

.

An apportionment method may return a set of apportionment vectors (in other words: it is a multivalued function). This is required, since in some cases there is no fair way to distinguish between two possible solutions. For example, if

h=101

(or any other odd number) and

t1=t2=1/2

, then (50,51) and (51,50) are both equally reasonable solutions, and there is no mathematical way to choose one over the other. While such ties are extremely rare in practice, the theory must account for them (in practice, when an apportionment method returns multiple outputs, one of them may be chosen by some external priority rules, or by coin flipping, but this is beyond the scope of the mathematical apportionment theory).

An apportionment method is denoted by a multivalued function

M(t,h)

; a particular

M

-solution is a single-valued function

f(t,h)

which selects a single apportionment from

M(t,h)

.

A partial apportionment method is an apportionment method for specific fixed values of

n

and

h

; it is a multivalued function

M*(t)

that accepts only

n

-vectors.

Variants

Sometimes, the input also contains a vector of integers

r1,\ldots,rn

representing minimum requirements -

ri

represents the smallest number of items that agent

i

should receive, regardless of its entitlement. So there is an additional requirement on the output:

ai\geqri

for all

i

.

When the agents are political parties, these numbers are usually 0, so this vector is omitted. But when the agents are states or districts, these numbers are often positive in order to ensure that all are represented. They can be the same for all agents (e.g. 1 for USA states, 2 for France districts), or different (e.g. in Canada or the European parliament).

Sometimes there is also a vector of maximum requirements, but this is less common.

Basic requirements

There are basic properties that should be satisfied by any reasonable apportionment method. They were given different names by different authors: the names on the left are from Pukelsheim; The names in parentheses on the right are from Balinsky and Young.

t'

is any permutation of

t

, then the apportionments in

M(t',h)

are exactly the corresponding permutations of the apportionments in

M(t,h)

.

ti=tj

implies

ai\geqaj-1

.

ti>tj

implies

ai\geqaj

.

M(ct,h)=M(t,h)

for every constant c (this is automatically satisfied if the input to the apportionment method is normalized).

t

, if the quota

qi=tih

of each agent

i

is an integer number, then

M(t,h)

must contain a unique vector

(q1,\ldots,qn)

. In other words, if an h-apportionment

a

is exactly proportional to

t

, then it should be the unique element of

M(t,h)

.

(q1,\ldots,qn)

, then the only allocation vector in all elements of the sequence is

(q1,\ldots,qn)

. To see the difference from weak exactness, consider the following rule. (a) Give each agent its quota rounded down,

\lfloorqi\rfloor

; (b) give the remaining seats iteratively to the largest parties. This rule is weakly exact, but not strongly exact. For example, suppose h=6 and consider the sequence of quota vectors (4+1/k, 2-1/k). The above rule yields the allocation (5,1) for all k, even though the limit when k→∞ is the integer vector (4,2).

a'\inM(t,h')

, and

h<h'

, and there is some h-apportionment

a

that is exactly proportional to

a'

, then it should be the unique element of

M(t,h)

. For example, if one solution in

M(t,6)

is (3,3), then the only solution in

M(t,4)

must be (2,2).

a

is returned for a converging sequence of entitlement vectors, then

a

is also returned for their limit vector. In other words, the set

\{t|a\inM(t,h)\}

- the set of entitlement vectors for which

a

is a possible apportionment - is topologically closed. An incomplete method can be "completed" by adding the apportionment

a

to any limit entitlement if and only if it belongs to every entitlement in the sequence. The completion of a symmetric and proportional apportionment method is complete, symmetric and proportional.

Other considerations

The proportionality of apportionment can be measured by seats-to-votes ratio and Gallagher index. The proportionality of apportionment together with electoral thresholds impact political fragmentation and barrier to entry to the political competition.[9]

Common apportionment methods

There are many apportionment methods, and they can be classified into several approaches.

  1. Largest remainder methods start by computing the vector of quotas rounded down, that is,

\lfloorq1\rfloor,\ldots,\lfloorqn\rfloor

. If the sum of these rounded values is exactly

h

, then this vector is returned as the unique apportionment. Typically, the sum is smaller than

h

. In this case, the remaining items are allocated among the agents according to their remainders

qi-\lfloorqi\rfloor

: the agent with the largest remainder receives one seat, then the agent with the second-largest remainder receives one seat, and so on, until all items are allocated. There are several variants of the LR method, depending on which quota is used:

tih

. Using LR with the Hare quota leads to Hamilton's method.

ti(h+1)

. The quotas in this method are larger, so there are fewer remaining items. In theory, it is possible that the sum of rounded-down quotas would be

h+1

which is larger than

h

, but this rarely happens in practice.
  1. Divisor methods, instead of using a fixed multiplier in the quota (such as

h

or

h+1

), choose the multiplier such that the sum of rounded quotas is exactly equal to

h

, so there are no remaining items to allocate. Formally,

M(t,h):=\{a|ai=\operatorname{round}(tiH)and

n
\sum
i=1

ai=hforsomerealnumberH\}.

Divisor methods differ by the method they use for rounding. A divisor method is parametrized by a divisor function

d(k)

which specifies, for each integer

k\geq0

, a real number in the interval

[k,k+1]

. It means that all numbers in

[k,d(k)]

should be rounded down to

k

, and all numbers in

[d(k),k+1]

should be rounded up to

k+1

. The rounding function is denoted by

\operatorname{round}d(x)

, and returns an integer

k

such that

d(k-1)\leqx\leqd(k)

. The number

d(k)

itself can be rounded both up and down, so the rounding function is multi-valued. For example, Adams' method uses

d(k)=k

, which corresponds to rounding up; D'Hondt/Jefferson method uses

d(k)=k+1

, which corresponds to rounding down; and Webster/Sainte-Laguë method uses

d(k)=k+0.5

, which corresponds to rounding to the nearest integer. A divisor method can also be computed iteratively: initially,

ai

is set to 0 for all parties. Then, at each iteration, the next seat is allocated to a party which maximizes the ratio
ti
d(ai)
.
  1. Rank-index methods are parametrized by a function

r(t,a)

which is decreasing in

a

. The apportionment is computed iteratively. Initially, set

ai

to 0 for all parties. Then, at each iteration, allocate the next seat to an agent which maximizes

r(ti,ai)

. Divisor methods are a special case of rank-index methods: a divisor method with divisor function

d(a)

is equivalent to a rank-index method with rank-index

r(t,a)=t/d(a)

.
  1. Optimization-based methods aim to attain, for each instance, an allocation that is "as fair as possible" for this instance. An allocation is "fair" if

ai=qi

for all agents i; in this case, we say that the "unfairness" of the allocation is 0. If this equality is violated, one can define a measure of "total unfairness", and try to minimize it. One can minimize the sum of unfairness levels, or the maximum unfairness level. Each optimization criterion leads to a different optimal apportionment rule.

Staying within the quota

See main article: Quota rule. The exact quota of agent

i

is

qi=tih

. A basic requirement from an apportionment method is that it allocates to each agent

i

its quota

qi

if it is an integer; otherwise, it should allocate it an integer that is near the exact quota, that is, either its lower quota

\lfloorqi\rfloor

or its upper quota

\lceilqi\rceil

.[10] We say that an apportionment method -

ai\geq\lfloorqi\rfloor

for all

i

(this holds iff

ai+1>qi

).

ai\leq\lceilqi\rceil

for all

i

(this holds iff

ai-1<qi

).
qi
ai+1

<1<

qi
ai-1

).

Hamilton's largest-remainder method satisfies both lower quota and upper quota by construction. This does not hold for the divisor methods.

Therefore, no divisor method satisfies both upper quota and lower quota for any number of agents. The uniqueness of Jefferson and Adams holds even in the much larger class of rank-index methods.

This can be seen as a disadvantage of divisor methods, but it can also be considered a disadvantage of the quota criterion:

"For example, to give D 26 instead of 25 seats in Table 10.1 would mean taking a seat from one of the smaller states A, B, or C. Such a transfer would penalize the per capita representation of the small state much more - in both absolute and relative terms - than state D is penalized by getting one less than its lower quota. Similar examples can be invented in which some state might reasonably get more than its upper quota. It can be argued that staying within the quota is not really compatible with the idea of proportionality at all, since it allows a much greater variance in the per capita representation of smaller states than it does for larger states."
In Monte-Carlo simulations, Webster's method satisfies both quotas with a very high probability. Moreover, Webster's method is the only division method that satisfies near quota: there are no agents

i,j

such that moving a seat from

i

to

j

would bring both of them nearer to their quotas:

qi-(ai-1)~<~ai-qi~~and~~(aj+1)-qj~<~qj-aj

.
Jefferson's method can be modified to satisfy both quotas, yielding the Quota-Jefferson method. Moreover, any divisor method can be modified to satisfy both quotas.[11] This yields the Quota-Webster method, Quota-Hill method, etc. This family of methods is often called the quatatone methods, as they satisfy both quotas and house-monotonicity.

Minimizing pairwise inequality

One way to evaluate apportionment methods is by whether they minimize the amount of inequality between pairs of agents. Clearly, inequality should take into account the different entitlements: if

ai/ti=aj/tj

then the agents are treated "equally" (w.r.t. to their entitlements); otherwise, if

ai/ti>aj/tj

then agent

i

is favored, and if

ai/ti<aj/tj

then agent

j

is favored. However, since there are 16 ways to rearrange the equality

ai/ti=aj/tj

, there are correspondingly many ways by which inequality can be defined.

|ai/ti-aj/tj|

. Webster's method is the unique apportionment method in which, for each pair of agents

i

and

j

, this difference is minimized (that is, moving a seat from

i

to

j

or vice versa would not make the difference smaller).

ai-(ti/tj)aj

for

ai/ti\geqaj/tj

This leads to Adams's method.

ai(tj/ti)-aj

for

ai/ti\geqaj/tj

. This leads to Jefferson's method.

|ti/ai-tj/aj|

. This leads to Dean's method.
\left|ai/ti
aj/tj

-1\right|

. This leads to the Huntington-Hill method.This analysis was done by Huntington in the 1920s.[12] [13] [14] Some of the possibilities do not lead to a stable solution. For example, if we define inequality as

|ai/aj-ti/tj|

, then there are instances in which, for any allocation, moving a seat from one agent to another might decrease their pairwise inequality. There is an example with 3 states with populations (737,534,329) and 16 seats.

Bias towards large/small agents

See main article: Seat bias. The seat bias of an apportionment is the tendency of an apportionment method to systematically favor either large or small parties. Jefferson's method and Droop's method are heavily biased in favor of large states; Adams' method is biased in favor of small states; and the Webster and Huntington–Hill methods are effectively unbiased toward either large or small states.

Consistency properties

Consistency properties are properties that characterize an apportionment method, rather than a particular apportionment. Each consistency property compares the outcomes of a particular method on different inputs. Several such properties have been studied.

State-population monotonicity means that, if the entitlement of an agent increases, its apportionment should not decrease. The name comes from the setting where the agents are federal states, whose entitlements are determined by their population. A violation of this property is called the population paradox. There are several variants of this property. One variant - the pairwise PM - is satisfied exclusively by divisor methods. That is, an apportionment method is pairwise PM if-and-only-if it is a divisor method.

When

n\geq4

and

h\geqn+3

, no partial apportionment method satisfies pairwise-PM, lower quota and upper quota. Combined with the previous statements, it implies that no divisor method satisfies both quotas.

House monotonicity means that, when the total number of seats

h

increases, no agent loses a seat. The violation of this property is called the Alabama paradox. It was considered particularly important in the early days of the USA, when the congress size increased every ten years. House-monotonicity is weaker than pairwise-PM. All rank-index methods (hence all divisor methods) are house-monotone - this clearly follows from the iterative procedure. Besides the divisor methods, there are other house-monotone methods, and some of them also satisfy both quotas. For example, the Quota method of Balinsky and Young satisfies house-monotonicity and upper-quota by construction, and it can be proved that it also satisfies lower-quota. It can be generalized: there is a general algorithm that yields all apportionment methods which are both house-monotone and satisfy both quotas. However, all these quota-based methods (Quota-Jefferson, Quota-Hill, etc.) may violate pairwise-PM: there are examples in which one agent gains in population but loses seats.

Uniformity (also called coherence) means that, if we take some subset of the agents

1,\ldots,k

, and apply the same method to their combined allocation

hk=a1+ … +ak

, then the result is the vector

(a1,\ldots,ak)

. All rank-index methods (hence all divisor methods) are uniform, since they assign seats to agents in a pre-determined method - determined by

r(t,a)

, and this order does not depend on the presence or absence of other agents. Moreover, every uniform method that is also anonymous and balanced must be a rank-index method.

Every uniform method that is also anonymous, weakly-exact and concordant (=

ti>tj

implies

ai\geqaj

) must be a divisor method. Moreover, among all anonymous methods:[15]

Encouraging coalitions

When the agents are political parties, they often split or merge. How such splitting/merging affects the apportionment will impact political fragmentation. Suppose a certain apportionment method gives two agents

i,j

some

ai,aj

seats respectively, and then these two agents form a coalition, and the method is re-activated.

ai+aj

seats (in other words, it is split-proof - a party cannot gain a seat by splitting).

ai+aj

seats (in other words, it is merge-proof - two parties cannot gain a seat by merging).

Among the divisor methods:

Since these are different methods, no divisor method gives every coalition of

i,j

exactly

ai+aj

seats. Moreover, this uniqueness can be extended to the much larger class of rank-index methods.

A weaker property, called "coalitional-stability", is that every coalition of

i,j

should receive between

ai+aj-1

and

ai+aj+1

seats; so a party can gain at most one seat by merging/splitting.

d

is coalitionally-stable iff

d(a1+a2)\leqd(a1)+d(a2)\leqd(a1+a2+1)

; this holds for all five standard divisor methods.

Moreover, every method satisfying both quotas is "almost coalitionally-stable" - it gives every coalition between

ai+aj-2

and

ai+aj+2

seats.

Summary table

The following table summarizes uniqueness results for classes of apportionment methods. For example, the top-left cell states that Jefferson's method is the unique divisor method satisfying the lower quota rule.

Lower quotaUpper quotaNear QuotaHouse monotonicityUniformityPopulation MonotonicSplitproofMergeproof
Divisor rulesJeffersonAdamsWebsterAnyAnyAnyJeffersonAdams
Rank-index rulesJeffersonAdamsWebsterDivisor rulesAnyDivisor rulesJeffersonAdams
Quota rulesAnyAnyAnyNoneNoneNone
Quota-capped divisor rulesYesYesYesYesNoneNone

Implementations

See also

Notes and References

  1. Book: COTTERET J. M. LES SYSTEMES ELECTORAUX. C. EMERI. 1973.
  2. Csoka. Péter. Herings. P. Jean-Jacques. 2016-01-01. Decentralized Clearing in Financial Networks (RM/16/005-revised-). Research Memorandum . en.
  3. Chakraborty . Mithun . Segal-Halevi . Erel . Suksompong . Warut . 2022-06-28 . Weighted Fairness Notions for Indivisible Items Revisited . Proceedings of the AAAI Conference on Artificial Intelligence . en . 36 . 5 . 4949–4956 . 2112.04166 . 10.1609/aaai.v36i5.20425 . 2374-3468 . free.
  4. Chakraborty . Mithun . Schmidt-Kraepelin . Ulrike . Suksompong . Warut . 2021-12-01 . Picking sequences and monotonicity in weighted fair division . Artificial Intelligence . 301 . 103578 . 2104.14347 . 10.1016/j.artint.2021.103578 . 0004-3702 . 233443832.
  5. 1994-01-01. Chapter 15 Apportionment. Handbooks in Operations Research and Management Science. en. 6. 529–560. 10.1016/S0927-0507(05)80096-9. 0927-0507. Balinski. M.L.. Young. H.P.. 9780444892041.
  6. Diaconis . Persi . Freedman . David . 1979-06-01 . On Rounding Percentages . Journal of the American Statistical Association . 74 . 366a . 359–364 . 10.1080/01621459.1979.10482518 . 0162-1459.
  7. Book: Balinski. Michel L.. Fair Representation: Meeting the Ideal of One Man, One Vote. Young. H. Peyton. Yale University Press. 1982. 0-300-02724-9. New Haven. registration.
  8. 2016-09-01. The whole and its parts: On the coherence theorem of Balinski and Young. Mathematical Social Sciences. en. 83. 11–19. 10.1016/j.mathsocsci.2016.06.001. 0165-4896. Palomares. Antonio. Pukelsheim. Friedrich. Ramírez. Victoriano.
  9. http://www.jstor.org/stable/1816288 Tullock, Gordon. "Entry barriers in politics." The American Economic Review 55.1/2 (1965): 458-466.
  10. Balinski. M. L.. Young. H. P.. 1975-08-01. The Quota Method of Apportionment. The American Mathematical Monthly. 82. 7. 701–730. 10.1080/00029890.1975.11993911. 0002-9890.
  11. Still. Jonathan W.. 1979-10-01. A Class of New Methods for Congressional Apportionment. SIAM Journal on Applied Mathematics. 37. 2. 401–418. 10.1137/0137031. 0036-1399.
  12. Huntington. E. V.. 1928. The Apportionment of Representatives in Congress. Transactions of the American Mathematical Society. 30. 1. 85–110. 10.2307/1989268. 1989268. 0002-9947. free.
  13. Huntington. Edward V.. 1921-09-01. A New Method of Apportionment of Representatives. Quarterly Publications of the American Statistical Association. 17. 135. 859–870. 10.1080/15225445.1921.10503487. 129746319 . 1522-5445.
  14. Huntington. Edward V.. 1921-04-01. The Mathematical Theory of the Apportionment of Representatives. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences of the United States of America. 7. 4. 123–127. 10.1073/pnas.7.4.123. 0027-8424. 1084767. 16576591. 1921PNAS....7..123H. free.
  15. Balinski. M. L.. Young. H. P.. 1978-09-01. Stability, Coalitions and Schisms in Proportional Representation Systems*. American Political Science Review. en. 72. 3. 848–858. 10.2307/1955106. 1955106. 144161027 . 0003-0554.
  16. Balinski. M. L.. Young. H. P.. 1979-02-01. Criteria for Proportional Representation. Operations Research. 27. 1. 80–95. 10.1287/opre.27.1.80. 0030-364X.
  17. Lang . Jérôme . Skowron . Piotr . 2018-10-01 . Multi-attribute proportional representation . Artificial Intelligence . en . 263 . 74–106 . 1509.03389 . 10.1016/j.artint.2018.07.005 . 0004-3702 . 11079872 . free.
  18. Spencer . Bruce D. . 1985-12-01 . Statistical Aspects of Equitable Apportionment . Journal of the American Statistical Association . 80 . 392 . 815–822 . 10.1080/01621459.1985.10478188 . 0162-1459.