\alpha1 | |
Q(e |
,...,
\alphan | |
e |
)
Q
An equivalent formulation, is the following: This equivalence transforms a linear relation over the algebraic numbers into an algebraic relation over
Q
The theorem is named for Ferdinand von Lindemann and Karl Weierstrass. Lindemann proved in 1882 that is transcendental for every non-zero algebraic number thereby establishing that is transcendental (see below). Weierstrass proved the above more general statement in 1885.
The theorem, along with the Gelfond–Schneider theorem, is extended by Baker's theorem, and all of these would be further generalized by Schanuel's conjecture.
The theorem is also known variously as the Hermite–Lindemann theorem and the Hermite–Lindemann–Weierstrass theorem. Charles Hermite first proved the simpler theorem where the exponents are required to be rational integers and linear independence is only assured over the rational integers,[1] a result sometimes referred to as Hermite's theorem.[2] Although that appears to be a special case of the above theorem, the general result can be reduced to this simpler case. Lindemann was the first to allow algebraic numbers into Hermite's work in 1882.[3] Shortly afterwards Weierstrass obtained the full result,[4] and further simplifications have been made by several mathematicians, most notably by David Hilbert[5] and Paul Gordan.[6]
The transcendence of and are direct corollaries of this theorem.
Suppose is a non-zero algebraic number; then is a linearly independent set over the rationals, and therefore by the first formulation of the theorem is an algebraically independent set; or in other words is transcendental. In particular, is transcendental. (A more elementary proof that is transcendental is outlined in the article on transcendental numbers.)
Alternatively, by the second formulation of the theorem, if is a non-zero algebraic number, then is a set of distinct algebraic numbers, and so the set is linearly independent over the algebraic numbers and in particular cannot be algebraic and so it is transcendental.
To prove that is transcendental, we prove that it is not algebraic. If were algebraic, i would be algebraic as well, and then by the Lindemann–Weierstrass theorem (see Euler's identity) would be transcendental, a contradiction. Therefore is not algebraic, which means that it is transcendental.
A slight variant on the same proof will show that if is a non-zero algebraic number then and their hyperbolic counterparts are also transcendental.
An analogue of the theorem involving the modular function was conjectured by Daniel Bertrand in 1997, and remains an open problem.[7] Writing for the square of the nome and the conjecture is as follows.
The proof relies on two preliminary lemmas. Notice that Lemma B itself is already sufficient to deduce the original statement of Lindemann–Weierstrass theorem.
Proof of Lemma A. To simplify the notation set:
\begin{align} &n0=0,&&\\ &ni
i | |
=\sum\nolimits | |
k=1 |
m(k),&&i=1,\ldots,r\\ &n=nr,&&\\ &
\alpha | |
ni-1+j |
=\gamma(i)j,&&1\leqi\leqr, 1\leqj\leqm(i)\\ &
\beta | |
ni-1+j |
=c(i). \end{align}
Then the statement becomes
n | |
\sum | |
k=1 |
\betak
\alphak | |
e |
≠ 0.
Let be a prime number and define the following polynomials:
fi(x)=
| |||||||||||||||||||
(x-\alphai) |
,
where is a non-zero integer such that
\ell\alpha1,\ldots,\ell\alphan
Ii(s)=
s | |
\int | |
0 |
es-xfi(x)dx.
Using integration by parts we arrive at
Ii(s)=es
np-1 | |
\sum | |
j=0 |
(j) | |
f | |
i |
(0)-
np-1 | |
\sum | |
j=0 |
(j) | |
f | |
i |
(s),
where
np-1
fi
(j) | |
f | |
i |
fi
-es-x
np-1 | |
\sum | |
j=0 |
(j) | |
f | |
i |
(x)
is a primitive of
es-xfi(x)
Consider the following sum:
\begin{align} Ji
n\beta | |
&=\sum | |
k |
Ii(\alphak)\\[5pt] &=
n\beta | |
\sum | |
k |
\left(
\alphak | |
e |
np-1 | |
\sum | |
j=0 |
(j) | |
f | |
i |
(0)-
np-1 | |
\sum | |
j=0 |
(j) | |
f | |
i |
(\alphak)\right)
np-1 | |
\\[5pt] &=\left(\sum | |
j=0 |
(j) | |
f | |
i |
n | |
(0)\right)\left(\sum | |
k=1 |
\betak
\alphak | |
e |
np-1 | |
\right)-\sum | |
j=0 |
\betakf
(j) | |
i |
(\alphak)\\[5pt] &=
n | |
-\sum | |
k=1 |
np-1 | |
\sum | |
j=0 |
\betakf
(j) | |
i |
(\alphak) \end{align}
In the last line we assumed that the conclusion of the Lemma is false. In order to complete the proof we need to reach a contradiction. We will do so by estimating
|J1 … Jn|
First
(j) | |
f | |
i |
(\alphak)
j\geqp
j<p
j=p-1
k=i
\ellnp(p-1)!\prodk ≠ (\alphai-\alpha
p. | |
k) |
This is not divisible by p when p is large enough because otherwise, putting
\deltai=\prodk ≠ (\ell\alphai-\ell\alphak)
(which is a non-zero algebraic integer) and calling
di\inZ
p | |
\ell | |
i |
So
Ji
Ji=-\sum
np-1 | |
j=0 |
r | |
\sum | |
t=1 |
(j) | |
c(t)\left(f | |
i |
(\alpha | |
nt-1+1 |
)+ … +
(j) | |
f | |
i |
(\alpha | |
nt |
)\right).
Since each
fi(x)
(x-\alphai)
fi(x)=\sum
np-1 | |
m=0 |
gm(\alpha
m, | |
i)x |
where
gm
(j) | |
f | |
i |
(x)
Hence, by the fundamental theorem of symmetric polynomials,
(j) | |
f | |
i |
(\alpha | |
nt-1+1 |
(j) | |
)+ … +f | |
i |
(\alpha | |
nt |
)
is a fixed polynomial with rational coefficients evaluated in
\alphai
\alpha | |
nt-1+1 |
,...,\alpha | |
nt |
Ji
G(\alphai)
Finally
J1 … Jn=G(\alpha1) … G(\alphan)
(p-1)!n
Ji
(p-1)!
|J1 … Jn|\geq(p-1)!n.
However one clearly has:
|Ii(\alphak)|\leq
|\alphak| | |
|\alpha | |
k|e |
Fi(|\alphak|),
where is the polynomial whose coefficients are the absolute values of those of fi (this follows directly from the definition of
Ii(s)
|Ji|\leq
n | |
\sum | |
k=1 |
\left|\betak\alphak\right
|\alphak| | |
|e |
Fi\left(\left|\alphak\right|\right)
and so by the construction of the
fi
|J1 … Jn|\leCp
Proof of Lemma B: Assuming
b(1)e\gamma(1)+ … +b(n)e\gamma(n)=0,
we will derive a contradiction, thus proving Lemma B.
Let us choose a polynomial with integer coefficients which vanishes on all the
\gamma(k)
\gamma(1),\ldots,\gamma(n),\gamma(n+1),\ldots,\gamma(N)
The polynomial
P(x1,...,xN)=\prod
\sigma\inSN |
(b(1)x\sigma(1)+ … +b(N)x\sigma(N))
vanishes at
(e\gamma(1),...,e\gamma(N))
\tau\inSN
h1 | |
x | |
\tau(1) |
…
hN | |
x | |
\tau(N) |
h1 | |
x | |
1 |
…
hN | |
x | |
N |
Thus, expanding
P(e\gamma(1),...,e\gamma(N))
h1\gamma(1)+...+hN\gamma(N)
So we are in the situation of Lemma A. To reach a contradiction it suffices to see that at least one of the coefficients is non-zero. This is seen by equipping with the lexicographic order and by choosing for each factor in the product the term with non-zero coefficient which has maximum exponent according to this ordering: the product of these terms has non-zero coefficient in the expansion and does not get simplified by any other term. This proves Lemma B. ∎
We turn now to prove the theorem: Let a(1), ..., a(n) be non-zero algebraic numbers, and α(1), ..., α(n) distinct algebraic numbers. Then let us assume that:
a(1)e\alpha(1)+ … +a(n)e\alpha(n)=0.
We will show that this leads to contradiction and thus prove the theorem. The proof is very similar to that of Lemma B, except that this time the choices are made over the a(i)'s:
For every i ∈, a(i) is algebraic, so it is a root of an irreducible polynomial with integer coefficients of degree d(i). Let us denote the distinct roots of this polynomial a(i)1, ..., a(i)d(i), with a(i)1 = a(i).
Let S be the functions σ which choose one element from each of the sequences (1, ..., d(1)), (1, ..., d(2)), ..., (1, ..., d(n)), so that for every 1 ≤ i ≤ n, σ(i) is an integer between 1 and d(i). We form the polynomial in the variables
x11,...,x1d(1),...,xn1,...,xnd(n),y1,...,yn
Q(x11,...,xnd(n),y1,...,yn)=\prod\nolimits\sigma\in\left(x1\sigma(1)y1+...+xn\sigma(n)yn\right).
Since the product is over all the possible choice functions σ, Q is symmetric in
xi1,...,xid(i)
a(i)1,...,a(i)d(i)
The evaluated polynomial
Q(a(1)1,...,a(n)d(n),e\alpha(1),...,e\alpha(n))
b(1)e\beta(1)+b(2)e\beta(2)+ … +b(N)e\beta(N)=0,
where we already grouped the terms with the same exponent. So in the left-hand side we have distinct values β(1), ..., β(N), each of which is still algebraic (being a sum of algebraic numbers) and coefficients
b(1),...,b(N)\inQ
\alpha(i)
e|S|\alpha(i)
By multiplying the equation with an appropriate integer factor, we get an identical equation except that now b(1), ..., b(N) are all integers. Therefore, according to Lemma B, the equality cannot hold, and we are led to a contradiction which completes the proof. ∎
Note that Lemma A is sufficient to prove that e is irrational, since otherwise we may write e = p / q, where both p and q are non-zero integers, but by Lemma A we would have qe − p ≠ 0, which is a contradiction. Lemma A also suffices to prove that is irrational, since otherwise we may write = k / n, where both k and n are integers) and then ±i are the roots of n2x2 + k2 = 0; thus 2 − 1 − 1 = 2e0 + ei + e−i ≠ 0; but this is false.
Similarly, Lemma B is sufficient to prove that e is transcendental, since Lemma B says that if a0, ..., an are integers not all of which are zero, then
0\ne | |
a | |
0e |
0.
Lemma B also suffices to prove that is transcendental, since otherwise we would have 1 + ei ≠ 0.
Baker's formulation of the theorem clearly implies the first formulation. Indeed, if
\alpha(1),\ldots,\alpha(n)
\Q
P(x1,\ldots,xn)=\sum
b | |
i1,\ldots,in |
i1 | |
x | |
1 |
…
in | |
x | |
n |
is a polynomial with rational coefficients, then we have
P\left(e\alpha(1),...,e\alpha(n)\right)=\sum
b | |
i1,...,in |
i1\alpha(1)+ … +in\alpha(n) | |
e |
,
and since
\alpha(1),\ldots,\alpha(n)
i1\alpha(1)+ … +in\alpha(n)
(i1,...,in)
b | |
i1,\ldots,in |
=0
(i1,...,in)
Now assume that the first formulation of the theorem holds. For
n=1
n>1
a(1),\ldots,a(n)
\alpha(1),\ldots,\alpha(n)
a(1)e\alpha(1)+ … +a(n)e\alpha(n)=0.
As seen in the previous section, and with the same notation used there, the value of the polynomial
Q(x11,\ldots,xnd(n),y1,...,yn)=\prod\nolimits\sigma\in\left(x1\sigma(1)y1+...+xn\sigma(n)yn\right),
at
\left(a(1)1,\ldots,a(n)d(n),e\alpha(1),\ldots,e\alpha(n)\right)
has an expression of the form
b(1)e\beta(1)+b(2)e\beta(2)+ … +b(M)e\beta(M)=0,
where we have grouped the exponentials having the same exponent. Here, as proved above,
b(1),\ldots,b(M)
\beta(m)
\alpha(i)
n>1
\alpha(1),\ldots,\alpha(n)
\Q
V
\C
\alpha(1),\ldots,\alpha(n)
\alpha(i1),\ldots,\alpha(ik)
V.
m=1,...,M
\begin{align} \beta(m)=qm,1\alpha(i1)+ … +qm,k\alpha(ik),&&qm,j=
cm,j | |
dm,j |
; cm,j,dm,j\in\Z. \end{align}
For each
j=1,\ldots,k,
dj
dm,j
m=1,\ldots,M
vj=\tfrac{1}{dj}\alpha(ij)
v1,\ldots,vk
V
\beta(m)
vj
b(1)e\beta(1)+b(2)e\beta(2)+ … +b(M)e\beta(M)=0,
by
N(v1+ … +vk) | |
e |
N
v1 | |
e |
vk | |
, … ,e |
A variant of Lindemann–Weierstrass theorem in which the algebraic numbers are replaced by the transcendental Liouville numbers (or in general, the U numbers) is also known.[9]