Leibniz operator explained

In abstract algebraic logic, a branch of mathematical logic, the Leibniz operator is a tool used to classify deductive systems, which have a precise technical definition and capture a large number of logics. The Leibniz operator was introduced by Wim Blok and Don Pigozzi, two of the founders of the field, as a means to abstract the well-known Lindenbaum–Tarski process, that leads to the association of Boolean algebras to classical propositional calculus, and make it applicable to as wide a variety of sentential logics as possible. It is an operator that assigns to a given theory of a given sentential logic, perceived as a term algebra with a consequence operation on its universe, the largest congruence on the algebra that is compatible with the theory.

Formulation

In this article, we introduce the Leibniz operator in the special case of classical propositional calculus, then we abstract it to the general notion applied to an arbitrary sentential logic and, finally, we summarize some of the most important consequences of its use in the theory of abstract algebraic logic.

Let

l{S}=\langle{\rmFm},\vdashl{S

}\rangle denote the classical propositional calculus. According to the classical Lindenbaum–Tarski process, given a theory

T

of

l{S}

,if

\equivT

denotes the binary relation on the set of formulas of

l{S}

, defined by

\phi\equivT\psi

if and only if

T\vdashl{S

}\phi\leftrightarrow\psi, where

\leftrightarrow

denotes the usualclassical propositional equivalence connective, then

\equivT

turns out to be a congruenceon the formula algebra. Furthermore, the quotient

{\rmFm}/{\equivT

} is a Boolean algebraand every Boolean algebra may be formed in this way.

Thus, the variety of Boolean algebras, which is,in algebraic logic terminology, the equivalent algebraic semantics (algebraic counterpart)of classical propositional calculus, is the class ofall algebras formed by taking appropriate quotientsof term algebras by those special kinds ofcongruences.

Notice that the condition

T\vdashl{S

}\phi\leftrightarrow\psi

that defines

\phi\equivT\psi

is equivalent to the condition

for every formula

\chi

:

T\vdashl{S

}\phi\leftrightarrow\chi if and only if

T\vdashl{S

}\psi\leftrightarrow\chi.

Passing now to an arbitrary sentential logic

l{S}=\langle{\rmFm}, \vdashl{S

}\rangle,

given a theory

T

,the Leibniz congruence associated with

T

isdenoted by

\Omega(T)

and is defined, for all

\phi,\psi\in{\rmFm}

, by

\phi\Omega(T)\psi

if and only if, for every formula

\alpha(x,\vec{y})

containing a variable

x

and possibly other variables in the list

\vec{y}

,and all formulas

\vec{\chi}

forming a list of the same length as that of

\vec{y}

, we have that

T\vdashl{S

}\alpha(\phi,\vec) if and only if

T\vdashl{S

}\alpha(\psi,\vec).

It turns out that this binary relation is a congruence relation on the formula algebra and, in fact, may alternatively be characterized as the largest congruence on the formula algebra that is compatiblewith the theory

T

, in the sense that if

\phi\Omega(T)\psi

and

T\vdashl{S

}\phi, then we must have also

T\vdashl{S

}\psi. It is this congruence that plays the same role as the congruence used in the traditional Lindenbaum–Tarski process described above in the context of an arbitrary sentential logic.

It is not, however, the case that for arbitrary sentential logics the quotients of the term algebras by these Leibniz congruences over different theories yield all algebras in the class that forms the natural algebraic counterpart of the sentential logic. This phenomenon occurs only in the case of "nice" logics and one of the main goals of abstract algebraic logic is to make this vague notion of a logic being "nice", in this sense, mathematically precise.

The Leibniz operator

\Omega

is the operator that maps a theory

T

of a given logic to the Leibniz congruence

\Omega(T),

associated with the theory. Thus, formally,

\Omega:Th(l{S}) → {\rmCon}({\rmFm})

is a mapping from the collection

{\rmTh}(l{S})

of the theories of a sentential logic

l{S}

to the collection

{\rmCon}({\rmFm})

of all congruences on the formula algebra

{\rmFm}

of the sentential logic.

Hierarchy

The Leibniz operator and the study of various of its properties that may or may not be satisfied for particular sentential logics have given rise to what is now known as the abstract algebraic hierarchy or Leibniz hierarchy of sentential logics. Logics are classified in various levels of this hierarchy depending on how strong a tie exists between the logic and its algebraic counterpart.

The properties of the Leibniz operator that help classify the logics are monotonicity, injectivity, continuity and commutativity with inverse substitutions. For instance, protoalgebraic logics, forming the widest class in the hierarchy – i.e., the one that lies in the bottom of the hierarchy and contains all other classes – are characterized by the monotonicity of the Leibniz operator on their theories.Other notable classes are formed by the equivalential logics, the weakly algebraizable logics and the algebraizable logics, among others.

There is a generalization of the Leibniz operator, in the context of categorical abstract algebraic logic, that makes it possible to apply a wide variety of techniques that were previously applicable only in the sentential logic framework to logics formalized as

\pi

-institutions.The

\pi

-institution framework is significantly wider in scope than the framework of sentential logics because it allows incorporating multiple signatures and quantifiers in the language and it provides a mechanism for handling logics that are not syntactically based.

References