Kripke semantics (also known as relational semantics or frame semantics, and often confused with possible world semantics)[1] is a formal semantics for non-classical logic systems created in the late 1950s and early 1960s by Saul Kripke and André Joyal. It was first conceived for modal logics, and later adapted to intuitionistic logic and other non-classical systems. The development of Kripke semantics was a breakthrough in the theory of non-classical logics, because the model theory of such logics was almost non-existent before Kripke (algebraic semantics existed, but were considered 'syntax in disguise').
See main article: Modal logic.
The language of propositional modal logic consists of a countably infinite set of propositional variables, a set of truth-functional connectives (in this article
\to
\neg
\Box
\Diamond
\Box
\DiamondA:=\neg\Box\negA
A Kripke frame or modal frame is a pair
\langleW,R\rangle
A Kripke model is a triple
\langleW,R,\Vdash\rangle
\langleW,R\rangle
\Vdash
w\Vdash\negA
w\nVdashA
w\VdashA\toB
w\nVdashA
w\VdashB
w\Vdash\BoxA
u\VdashA
u
w R u
w\VdashA
\Vdash
A formula A is valid in:
\langleW,R,\Vdash\rangle
w\VdashA
\langleW,R\rangle
\langleW,R,\Vdash\rangle
\Vdash
We define Thm(C) to be the set of all formulas that are valid inC. Conversely, if X is a set of formulas, let Mod(X) be theclass of all frames which validate every formula from X.
A modal logic (i.e., a set of formulas) L is sound withrespect to a class of frames C, if L ⊆ Thm(C). L iscomplete wrt C if L ⊇ Thm(C).
Semantics is useful for investigating a logic (i.e. a derivation system) only if the semantic consequence relation reflects its syntactical counterpart, the syntactic consequence relation (derivability). It is vital to know which modal logics are sound and complete with respect to a class of Kripke frames, and to determine also which class that is.
For any class C of Kripke frames, Thm(C) is a normal modal logic (in particular, theorems of the minimal normal modal logic, K, are valid in every Kripke model). However, the converse does not hold in general: while most of the modal systems studied are complete of classes of frames described by simple conditions, Kripke incomplete normal modal logics do exist. A natural example of such a system is Japaridze's polymodal logic.
A normal modal logic L corresponds to a class of frames C, if C = Mod(L). In other words, C is the largest class of frames such that L is sound wrt C. It follows that L is Kripke complete if and only if it is complete of its corresponding class.
Consider the schema T :
\BoxA\toA
\langleW,R\rangle
w\Vdash\BoxA
w\VdashA
u\Vdashp
w\Vdash\Boxp
w\Vdashp
\Vdash
It is often much easier to characterize the corresponding class of L than to prove its completeness, thus correspondence serves as a guide to completeness proofs. Correspondence is also used to show incompleteness of modal logics: suppose L1 ⊆ L2 are normal modal logics that correspond to the same class of frames, but L1 does not prove all theorems of L2. Then L1 is Kripke incomplete. For example, the schema
\Box(A\leftrightarrow\Box A)\to\BoxA
\Box A\to\Box\BoxA
The following table lists common modal axioms together with their corresponding classes. The naming of the axioms often varies; Here, axiom K is named after Saul Kripke; axiom T is named after the truth axiom in epistemic logic; axiom D is named after deontic logic; axiom B is named after L. E. J. Brouwer; and axioms 4 and 5 are named based on C. I. Lewis's numbering of symbolic logic systems.
Name | Axiom | Frame condition | |
---|---|---|---|
K | \Box(A\toB)\to(\BoxA\to\BoxB) | holds true for any frames | |
T | \BoxA\toA | reflexive wRw | |
- | \Box\BoxA\to\BoxA | dense wRu ⇒ \existsv(wRv\landvRu) | |
4 | \BoxA\to\Box\BoxA | transitive wRv\wedgevRu ⇒ wRu | |
D | \BoxA\to\DiamondA \Diamond\top \neg\Box\bot | serial \forallw\existsv(wRv) | |
B | A\to\Box\DiamondA \Diamond\BoxA\toA | symmetric : wRv ⇒ vRw | |
5 | \DiamondA\to\Box\DiamondA | Euclidean wRu\landwRv ⇒ uRv | |
GL | \Box(\BoxA\toA)\to\BoxA | R transitive, R−1 well-founded | |
Grz[3] | \Box(\Box(A\to\BoxA)\toA)\toA | R reflexive and transitive, R−1−Id well-founded | |
H | \Box(\BoxA\toB)\lor\Box(\BoxB\toA) | wRu\landwRv ⇒ uRv\lorvRu | |
M | \Box\DiamondA\to\Diamond\BoxA | (a complicated second-order property) | |
G | \Diamond\BoxA\to\Box\DiamondA | convergent: wRu\landwRv ⇒ \existsx(uRx\landvRx) | |
- | A\to\BoxA | discrete: wRv ⇒ w=v | |
- | \DiamondA\to\BoxA | partial function wRu\landwRv ⇒ u=v | |
- | \DiamondA\leftrightarrow\BoxA | function: \forallw\exists!uwRu \exists | is the uniqueness quantification) |
- | \BoxA \Box\bot | empty: \forallw\forallu\neg(wRu) | |
\Box[(A\toB)\landA]\to\BoxB
Note that for axiom D,
\DiamondA
\Diamond\top
\DiamondA → \Diamond\top
For any normal modal logic, L, a Kripke model (called the canonical model) can be constructed that refutes precisely the non-theorems ofL, by an adaptation of the standard technique of using maximal consistent sets as models. Canonical Kripke models play a role similar to the Lindenbaum–Tarski algebra construction in algebraicsemantics.
A set of formulas is L-consistent if no contradiction can be derived from it using the theorems of L, and Modus Ponens. A maximal L-consistent set (an L-MCSfor short) is an L-consistent set that has no proper L-consistent superset.
The canonical model of L is a Kripke model
\langleW,R,\Vdash\rangle
\Vdash
X R Y
A
\BoxA\inX
A\inY
X\VdashA
A\inX
The main application of canonical models are completeness proofs. Properties of the canonical model of K immediately imply completeness of K with respect to the class of all Kripke frames.This argument does not work for arbitrary L, because there is no guarantee that the underlying frame of the canonical model satisfies the frame conditions of L.
We say that a formula or a set X of formulas is canonicalwith respect to a property P of Kripke frames, if
A union of canonical sets of formulas is itself canonical.It follows from the preceding discussion that any logic axiomatized bya canonical set of formulas is Kripke complete, andcompact.
The axioms T, 4, D, B, 5, H, G (and thusany combination of them) are canonical. GL and Grz are notcanonical, because they are not compact. The axiom M by itself isnot canonical (Goldblatt, 1991), but the combined logic S4.1 (infact, even K4.1) is canonical.
In general, it is undecidable whether a given axiom iscanonical. We know a nice sufficient condition: Henrik Sahlqvist identified a broad class of formulas (now calledSahlqvist formulas) such that
This is a powerful criterion: for example, all axiomslisted above as canonical are (equivalent to) Sahlqvist formulas.
A logic has the finite model property (FMP) if it is completewith respect to a class of finite frames. An application of thisnotion is the decidability question: itfollows fromPost's theorem that a recursively axiomatized modal logic Lwhich has FMP is decidable, provided it is decidable whether a givenfinite frame is a model of L. In particular, every finitelyaxiomatizable logic with FMP is decidable.
There are various methods for establishing FMP for a given logic.Refinements and extensions of the canonical model construction oftenwork, using tools such as filtration orunravelling. As another possibility,completeness proofs based on cut-freesequent calculi usually produce finite modelsdirectly.
Most of the modal systems used in practice (including all listed above) have FMP.
In some cases, we can use FMP to prove Kripke completeness of a logic:every normal modal logic is complete with respect to a class ofmodal algebras, and a finite modal algebra can be transformedinto a Kripke frame. As an example, Robert Bull proved using this methodthat every normal extension of S4.3 has FMP, and is Kripkecomplete.
See also: Multimodal logic.
Kripke semantics has a straightforward generalization to logics withmore than one modality. A Kripke frame for a language with
\{\Boxi\midi\inI\}
w\Vdash\BoxiA
\forallu(w Ri u ⇒ u\VdashA).
A simplified semantics, discovered by Tim Carlson, is often used forpolymodal provability logics. A Carlson model is a structure
\langleW,R,\{Di\}i\in,\Vdash\rangle
w\Vdash\BoxiA
\forallu\inDi(w R u ⇒ u\VdashA).
Carlson models are easier to visualize and to work with than usualpolymodal Kripke models; there are, however, Kripke complete polymodallogics which are Carlson incomplete.
Kripke semantics for intuitionistic logic follows the same principles as the semantics of modal logic, but it uses a different definition of satisfaction.
An intuitionistic Kripke model is a triple
\langleW,\le,\Vdash\rangle
\langleW,\le\rangle
\Vdash
w\leu
w\Vdashp
u\Vdashp
w\VdashA\landB
w\VdashA
w\VdashB
w\VdashA\lorB
w\VdashA
w\VdashB
w\VdashA\toB
u\gew
u\VdashA
u\VdashB
w\Vdash\bot
The negation of A, ¬A, could be defined as an abbreviation for A → ⊥. If for all u such that w ≤ u, not u ⊩ A, then w ⊩ A → ⊥ is vacuously true, so w ⊩ ¬A.
Intuitionistic logic is sound and complete with respect to its Kripkesemantics, and it has the finite model property.
Let L be a first-order language. A Kripkemodel of L is a triple
\langleW,\le,\{Mw\}w\in\rangle
\langleW,\le\rangle
Given an evaluation e of variables by elements of Mw, wedefine the satisfaction relation
w\VdashA[e]
w\VdashP(t1,...,tn)[e]
P(t1[e],...,tn[e])
w\Vdash(A\landB)[e]
w\VdashA[e]
w\VdashB[e]
w\Vdash(A\lorB)[e]
w\VdashA[e]
w\VdashB[e]
w\Vdash(A\toB)[e]
u\gew
u\VdashA[e]
u\VdashB[e]
w\Vdash\bot[e]
w\Vdash(\existsxA)[e]
a\inMw
w\VdashA[e(x\toa)]
w\Vdash(\forallxA)[e]
u\gew
a\inMu
u\VdashA[e(x\toa)]
As part of the independent development of sheaf theory, it was realised around 1965 that Kripke semantics was intimately related to the treatment of existential quantification in topos theory. That is, the 'local' aspect of existence for sections of a sheaf was a kind of logic of the 'possible'. Though this development was the work of a number of people, the name Kripke–Joyal semantics is often used in this connection.
As in classical model theory, there are methods forconstructing a new Kripke model from other models.
The natural homomorphisms in Kripke semantics are calledp-morphisms (which is short for pseudo-epimorphism, but thelatter term is rarely used). A p-morphism of Kripke frames
\langleW,R\rangle
\langleW',R'\rangle
f\colonW\toW'
A p-morphism of Kripke models
\langleW,R,\Vdash\rangle
\langleW',R',\Vdash'\rangle
f\colonW\toW'
w\Vdashp
f(w)\Vdash'p
P-morphisms are a special kind of bisimulations. In general, abisimulation between frames
\langleW,R\rangle
\langleW',R'\rangle
A bisimulation of models is additionally required to preserve forcingof atomic formulas:
if w B w’, then
w\Vdashp
w'\Vdash'p
We can transform a Kripke model into a tree usingunravelling. Given a model
\langleW,R,\Vdash\rangle
\langleW',R',\Vdash'\rangle
s=\langlew0,w1,...,wn\rangle
s\Vdashp
wn\Vdashp
\langlew0,w1,...,wn\rangle R' \langlew0,w1,...,wn,wn+1\rangle
Filtration is a useful construction which uses to prove FMP for many logics. Let X be a set offormulas closed under taking subformulas. An X-filtration of amodel
\langleW,R,\Vdash\rangle
\langleW',R',\Vdash'\rangle
u\Vdash\BoxA
\BoxA\inX
v\VdashA
u ≡X v if and only if for all A ∈ X,
u\VdashA
v\VdashA
The main defect of Kripke semantics is the existence of Kripke incomplete logics, and logics which are complete but not compact. It can be remedied by equipping Kripke frames with extra structure which restricts the set of possible valuations, using ideas from algebraic semantics. This gives rise to the general frame semantics.
See main article: Kripke structure, state transition system and model checking. Blackburn et al. (2001) point out that because a relational structure is simply a set together with a collection of relations on that set, it is unsurprising that relational structures are to be found just about everywhere. As an example from theoretical computer science, they give labeled transition systems, which model program execution. Blackburn et al. thus claim because of this connection that modal languages are ideally suited in providing "internal, local perspective on relational structures." (p. xii)
Similar work that predated Kripke's revolutionary semantic breakthroughs:
. Melvin Fitting. Intuitionistic Logic, Model Theory and Forcing . registration . 1969 . North-Holland . 978-0-444-53418-7.