In set theory, König's theorem states that if the axiom of choice holds, I is a set,
\kappai
λi
\kappai<λi
\sumi\kappai<\prodiλi.
The sum here is the cardinality of the disjoint union of the sets mi, and the product is the cardinality of the Cartesian product. However, without the use of the axiom of choice, the sum and the product cannot be defined as cardinal numbers, and the meaning of the inequality sign would need to be clarified.
König's theorem was introduced by in the slightly weaker form that the sum of a strictly increasing sequence of nonzero cardinal numbers is less than their product.
The precise statement of the result: if I is a set, Ai and Bi are sets for every i in I, and
Ai<Bi
\sumiAi<\prodiBi,
(Of course, König's theorem is trivial if the cardinal numbers mi and ni are finite and the index set I is finite. If I is empty, then the left sum is the empty sum and therefore 0, while the right product is the empty product and therefore 1).
König's theorem is remarkable because of the strict inequality in the conclusion. There are many easy rules for the arithmetic of infinite sums and products of cardinals in which one can only conclude a weak inequality ≤, for example: if
mi<ni
\sumimi\le\sumini,
mi=1
ni=2
\aleph0
\kappa
\kappa<2\kappa
One way of stating the axiom of choice is "an arbitrary Cartesian product of non-empty sets is non-empty". Let Bi be a non-empty set for each i in I. Let Ai = for each i in I. Thus by König's theorem, we have:
\foralli\inI(\{\}<Bi)
\{\}<\prodiBi
König's theorem has also important consequences for cofinality of cardinal numbers.
\kappa\ge\aleph0
\kappa<\kappa\operatorname{cf(\kappa)}
If κ is regular, then this follows from Cantor's theorem. If κ is singular, then κ is a limit cardinal. Choose a strictly increasing cf(κ)-sequence of cardinals approaching κ. Let λ be their sum. Each summand is less than κ, so, by König's theorem, λ is less than the product of cf(κ) copies of κ. We finish the proof by showing that λ = κ. Since each summand is a lower bound for λ, λ ≥ κ. For the other inequality, λ ≤ cf(κ)·κ = κ.
According to Easton's theorem, the next consequence of König's theorem is the only nontrivial constraint on the continuum function for regular cardinals.
\kappa\geq\aleph0
λ\geq2
\kappa<\operatorname{cf}(λ\kappa)
\mu=λ\kappa
\kappa\ge\operatorname{cf}(\mu)
\mu<\mu\operatorname{cf(\mu)}\le\mu\kappa=(λ\kappa)\kappa=λ\kappa=λ\kappa=\mu
Assuming Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory, including especially the axiom of choice, we can prove the theorem. Remember that we are given
\foralli\inI Ai<Bi
\sumi\inAi<\prodi\inBi.
The axiom of choice implies that the condition A < B is equivalent to the condition that there is no function from A onto B and B is nonempty.So we are given that there is no function from Ai onto Bi≠, and we have to show that any function f from the disjoint union of the As to the product of the Bs is not surjective and that the product is nonempty. That the product is nonempty follows immediately from the axiom of choice and the fact that the factors are nonempty. For each i choose a bi in Bi not in the image of Ai under the composition of f with the projection to Bi. Then the product of the elements bi is not in the image of f, so f does not map the disjoint union of the As onto the product of the Bs.