In social choice theory, the independence of (irrelevant) clones criterion says that adding a clone, i.e. a new candidate very similar to an already-existing candidate, should not spoil the results.[1] It can be considered a very weak form of the independence of irrelevant alternatives (IIA) criterion.
A group of candidates are called clones if they are always ranked together, placed side-by-side, by every voter; no voter ranks any of the non-clone candidates between or equal to the clones. In other words, the process of cloning a candidate involves taking an existing candidate C, then replacing them with several candidates C1, C2... who are slotted into the original ballots in the spot where C previously was, with the clones being arranged in any order. If a set of clones contains at least two candidates, the criterion requires that deleting one of the clones must not increase or decrease the winning chance of any candidate not in the set of clones.
Ranked pairs, the Schulze method, and any system that satisfies independence of irrelevant alternatives such as range voting or majority judgment satisfies the criterion. Instant-runoff voting is generally described as passing, but this may depend on specific details in how the criterion is defined and how tied ranks are handled.[2]
The Borda count, minimax, Kemeny–Young, Copeland's method, plurality, and the two-round system all fail the independence of clones criterion. Voting methods that limit the number of allowed ranks also fail the criterion, because the addition of clones can leave voters with insufficient space to express their preferences about other candidates. For similar reasons, ballot formats that impose such a limit may cause an otherwise clone-independent method to fail.
This criterion is very weak, as adding a substantially similar (but not quite identical) candidate to a race can still substantially affect the results and cause vote splitting. For example, the center squeeze pathology that affects instant-runoff voting means that several similar (but not identical) candidates competing in the same race will tend to hurt each others' chances of winning.[3]
Election methods that fail independence of clones can be clone negative (the addition of a similar candidate decreases another candidate's chance of winning) or clone positive (the addition of a similar candidate increases another candidate's chance of winning). First-preference plurality is a common example of such a method.
The Borda count is an example of a clone-positive method; in fact, the method is so clone-positive that any candidate can simply "clone their way to victory", and the winner being the coalition that runs the most clones. Plurality voting is an example of a strongly clone-negative method because of vote-splitting.
A method can also fail the independence of clones method without being clone-positive or clone-negative.
Finally, methods can suffer from crowding, which happens where cloning a losing candidate changes the winner from one non-clone to a different non-clone. Copeland's method is an example of a method that exhibits crowding.
See main article: Borda count.
Consider an election in which there are two candidates, A and B. Suppose the voters have the following preferences:
66%: A>B | 34%: B>A |
Candidate A would receive 66% Borda points (66%×1 + 34%×0) and B would receive 34% (66%×0 + 34%×1). Thus candidate A would win by a 66% landslide.
Now suppose supporters of B nominate an additional candidate, B2, that is very similar to B but considered inferior by all voters. For the 66% who prefer A, B continues to be their second choice. For the 34% who prefer B, A continues to be their least preferred candidate. Now the voters' preferences are as follows:
66%: A>B>B2 | 34%: B>B2>A |
Candidate A now has 132% Borda points (66%×2 + 34%×0). B has 134% (66%×1 + 34%×2). B2 has 34% (66%×0 + 34%×1). The nomination of B2 changes the winner from A to B, overturning the landslide, even though the additional information about voters' preferences is redundant due to the similarity of B2 to B.
Similar examples can be constructed to show that given the Borda count, any arbitrarily large landslide can be overturned by adding enough candidates (assuming at least one voter prefers the landslide loser). For example, to overturn a 90% landslide preference for A over B, add 9 alternatives similar/inferior to B. Then A's score would be 900% (90%×10 + 10%×0) and B's score would be 910% (90%×9 + 10%×10).
No knowledge of the voters' preferences is needed to exploit this strategy. Factions could simply nominate as many alternatives as possible that are similar to their preferred alternative.
In typical elections, game theory suggests this manipulability of Borda can be expected to be a serious problem, particularly when a significant number of voters can be expected to vote their sincere order of preference (as in public elections, where many voters are not strategically sophisticated; cite Michael R. Alvarez of Caltech). Small minorities typically have the power to nominate additional candidates, and typically it is easy to find additional candidates that are similar.
In the context of people running for office, people can take similar positions on the issues, and in the context of voting on proposals, it is easy to construct similar proposals. Game theory suggests that all factions would seek to nominate as many similar candidates as possible since the winner would depend on the number of similar candidates, regardless of the voters' preferences.
See main article: Copeland's method. These examples show that Copeland's method violates the Independence of clones criterion.
Copeland's method is vulnerable against crowding, that is the outcome of the election is changed by adding (non-winning) clones of a non-winning candidate. Assume five candidates A, B, B2, B3 and C and 4 voters with the following preferences:
| Preferences | |
---|---|---|
1 | A > B3 > B > B2 > C | |
1 | B3 > B > B2 > C > A | |
2 | C > A > B2 > B > B3 |
If only one of the clones would compete, preferences would be as follows:
| Preferences | |
---|---|---|
1 | A > B > C | |
1 | B > C > A | |
2 | C > A > B |
The results would be tabulated as follows:
X | ||||
A | B | C | ||
Y | A | [X] 1 [Y] 3 | [X] 3 [Y] 1 | |
B | [X] 3 [Y] 1 | [X] 2 [Y] 2 | ||
C | [X] 1 [Y] 3 | [X] 2 [Y] 2 | ||
Pairwise election results (won-tied-lost): | 1-0-1 | 0-1-1 | 1-1-0 |
Result: C has one win and no defeats, A has one win and one defeat. Thus, C is elected Copeland winner.
Assume, all three clones would compete. The preferences would be the following:
| Preferences | |
---|---|---|
1 | A > B3 > B > B2 > C | |
1 | B3 > B > B2 > C > A | |
2 | C > A > B2 > B > B3 |
The results would be tabulated as follows:
X | ||||||
A | B | B2 | B3 | C | ||
Y | A | [X] 1 [Y] 3 | [X] 1 [Y] 3 | [X] 1 [Y] 3 | [X] 3 [Y] 1 | |
B | [X] 3 [Y] 1 | [X] 2 [Y] 2 | [X] 2 [Y] 2 | [X] 2 [Y] 2 | ||
B2 | [X] 3 [Y] 1 | [X] 2 [Y] 2 | [X] 2 [Y] 2 | [X] 2 [Y] 2 | ||
B3 | [X] 3 [Y] 1 | [X] 2 [Y] 2 | [X] 2 [Y] 2 | [X] 2 [Y] 2 | ||
C | [X] 1 [Y] 3 | [X] 2 [Y] 2 | [X] 2 [Y] 2 | [X] 2 [Y] 2 | ||
Pairwise election results (won-tied-lost): | 3-0-1 | 0-3-1 | 0-3-1 | 0-3-1 | 1-3-0 |
Result: Still, C has one win and no defeat, but now A has three wins and one defeat. Thus, A is elected Copeland winner.
A benefits from the clones of the candidate he defeats, while C cannot benefit from the clones because C ties with all of them. Thus, by adding two clones of the non-winning candidate B, the winner has changed. Thus, Copeland's method is vulnerable against crowding and fails the independence of clones criterion.
Copeland's method is also vulnerable against teaming, that is adding clones raises the winning chances of the set of clones. Again, assume five candidates A, B, B2, B3 and C and 2 voters with the following preferences:
| Preferences | |
---|---|---|
1 | A > C > B > B3 > B2 | |
1 | B > B2 > B3 > A > C |
Assume that only one of the clones would compete. The preferences would be as follows:
| Preferences | |
---|---|---|
1 | A > C > B | |
1 | B > A > C |
The results would be tabulated as follows:
X | ||||
A | B | C | ||
Y | A | [X] 1 [Y] 1 | [X] 0 [Y] 2 | |
B | [X] 1 [Y] 1 | [X] 1 [Y] 1 | ||
C | [X] 2 [Y] 0 | [X] 1 [Y] 1 | ||
Pairwise election results (won-tied-lost): | 1-1-0 | 0-2-0 | 0-1-1 |
Result: A has one win and no defeats, B has no wins or defeats so A is elected Copeland winner.
If all three clones competed, the preferences would be as follows:
| Preferences | |
---|---|---|
1 | A > C > B > B3 > B2 | |
1 | B > B2 > B3 > A > C |
The results would be tabulated as follows:
X | ||||||
A | B | B2 | B3 | C | ||
Y | A | [X] 1 [Y] 1 | [X] 1 [Y] 1 | [X] 1 [Y] 1 | [X] 0 [Y] 2 | |
B | [X] 1 [Y] 1 | [X] 0 [Y] 2 | [X] 0 [Y] 2 | [X] 1 [Y] 1 | ||
B2 | [X] 1 [Y] 1 | [X] 2 [Y] 0 | [X] 1 [Y] 1 | [X] 1 [Y] 1 | ||
B3 | [X] 1 [Y] 1 | [X] 2 [Y] 0 | [X] 1 [Y] 1 | [X] 1 [Y] 1 | ||
C | [X] 2 [Y] 0 | [X] 1 [Y] 1 | [X] 1 [Y] 1 | [X] 1 [Y] 1 | ||
Pairwise election results (won-tied-lost): | 1-3-0 | 2-2-0 | 0-3-1 | 0-3-1 | 0-3-1 |
Result: A has one win and no defeat, but now B has two wins and no defeat. Thus, B is elected Copeland winner.
B benefits from adding inferior clones, while A cannot benefit from the clones because he ties with all of them. So, by adding two clones of B, B changed from loser to winner. Thus, Copeland's method is vulnerable against Teaming and fails the Independence of clones criterion.
See main article: Plurality voting system.
Suppose there are two candidates, A and B, and 55% of the voters prefer A over B. A would win the election, 55% to 45%. But suppose the supporters of B also nominate an alternative similar to A, named A2. Assume a significant number of the voters who prefer A over B also prefer A2 over A. When they vote for A2, this reduces A's total below 45%, causing B to win.
A 55% | A 30% | |
A2 not present | A2 25% | |
B 45% | B 45% |
See main article: Range voting.
Range voting satisfies the independence of clones criterion.
However, like in every voting system, if voters change their opinions about candidates if similar candidates are added, adding clone candidates can change the outcome of an election. This can be seen by some premises and a simple example:
In range voting, to raise the influence of the ballot, the voter can give the maximum possible score to their most preferred alternative and the minimum possible score to their least preferred alternative. In fact, giving the maximum possible score to all candidates that are over some threshold and giving the minimum possible score to the other candidates, will maximize the influence of a ballot on the outcome. However, for this example it is necessary that the voter uses the first simple rule, but not the second.
Begin by supposing there are 3 alternatives: A, B and B2, where B2 is similar to B but considered inferior by the supporters of A and B. The voters supporting A would have the order of preference "A>B>B2" so that they give A the maximum possible score, they give B2 the minimum possible score, and they give B a score that's somewhere in between (greater than the minimum). The supporters of B would have the order of preference "B>B2>A", so they give B the maximum possible score, A the minimum score and B2 a score somewhere in between. Assume B narrowly wins the election.
Now suppose B2 isn't nominated. The voters supporting A who would have given B a score somewhere in between would now give B the minimum score while the supporters of B will still give B the maximum score, changing the winner to A. This violates the criterion.Note, that if the voters that support B would prefer B2 to B, this result would not hold, since removing B2 would raise the score B receives from his supporters in an analogous way as the score he receives from the supporters of A would decrease.
The conclusion that can be drawn is that considering all voters voting in a certain special way, range voting creates an incentive to nominate additional alternatives that are similar to one you prefer, but considered clearly inferior by his voters and by the voters of his opponent, since this can be expected to cause the voters supporting the opponent to raise their score of the one you prefer (because it looks better by comparison to the inferior ones), but not his own voters to lower their score.
See main article: Kemeny–Young method.
This example shows that the Kemeny–Young method violates the Independence of clones criterion. Assume five candidates A, B1, B2, B3 and C and 13 voters with the following preferences:
| Preferences | |
---|---|---|
4 | A > B1 > B2 > B3 > C | |
5 | B1 > B2 > B3 > C > A | |
4 | C > A > B1 > B2 > B3 |
Assume only one of the clones competes. The preferences would be:
| Preferences | |
---|---|---|
4 | A > B1 > C | |
5 | B1 > C > A | |
4 | C > A > B1 |
The Kemeny–Young method arranges the pairwise comparison counts in the following tally table:
All possible pairs of choice names | Number of votes with indicated preference | ||||
---|---|---|---|---|---|
Prefer X over Y | Equal preference | Prefer Y over X | |||
X = A | Y = B1 | 8 | 0 | 5 | |
X = A | Y = C | 4 | 0 | 9 | |
X = B1 | Y = C | 9 | 0 | 4 |
The ranking scores of all possible rankings are:
Preferences | 1. vs 2. | 1. vs 3. | 2. vs 3. | Total | |
---|---|---|---|---|---|
A > B1 > C | 8 | 4 | 9 | 21 | |
A > C > B1 | 4 | 8 | 4 | 16 | |
B1 > A > C | 5 | 9 | 4 | 18 | |
B1 > C > A | 9 | 5 | 9 | 23 | |
C > A > B1 | 9 | 4 | 8 | 21 | |
C > B1 > A | 4 | 9 | 5 | 18 |
Result: The ranking B1 > C > A has the highest ranking score. Thus, B1 wins ahead of C and A.
Assume all three clones compete. The preferences would be:
| Preferences | |
---|---|---|
4 | A > B1 > B2 > B3 > C | |
5 | B1 > B2 > B3 > C > A | |
4 | C > A > B1 > B2 > B3 |
The Kemeny–Young method arranges the pairwise comparison counts in the following tally table (with
i\in\{1,2,3\}
All possible pairs of choice names | Number of votes with indicated preference | ||||
---|---|---|---|---|---|
Prefer X over Y | Equal preference | Prefer Y over X | |||
X = A | Y = Bi | 8 | 0 | 5 | |
X = A | Y = C | 4 | 0 | 9 | |
X = Bi | Y = C | 9 | 0 | 4 | |
X = B1 | Y = B2 | 13 | 0 | 0 | |
X = B1 | Y = B3 | 13 | 0 | 0 | |
X = B2 | Y = B3 | 13 | 0 | 0 |
Since the clones have identical results against all other candidates, they have to be ranked one after another in the optimal ranking. More over, the optimal ranking within the clones is unambiguous: B1 > B2 > B3. In fact, for computing the results, the three clones can be seen as one united candidate B, whose wins and defeats are three times as strong as of every single clone. The ranking scores of all possible rankings with respect to that are:
Preferences | 1. vs 2. | 1. vs 3. | 2. vs 3. | Total | |
---|---|---|---|---|---|
A > B > C | 24 | 4 | 27 | 55 | |
A > C > B | 4 | 24 | 12 | 40 | |
B > A > C | 15 | 27 | 4 | 46 | |
B > C > A | 27 | 15 | 9 | 51 | |
C > A > B | 9 | 12 | 24 | 45 | |
C > B > A | 12 | 9 | 15 | 36 |
Result: The ranking A > B1 > B2 > B3 > C has the highest ranking score. Thus, A wins ahead of the clones Bi and C.
A benefits from the two clones of B1 because A's win is multiplied by three. So, by adding two clones of B, B changed from winner to loser. Thus, the Kemeny–Young method is vulnerable against spoilers and fails the independence of clones criterion.
See main article: Minimax Condorcet. This example shows that the minimax method violates the Independence of clones criterion. Assume four candidates A, B1, B2 and B3 and 9 voters with the following preferences:
| Preferences | |
---|---|---|
3 | A > B1 > B2 > B3 | |
3 | B2 > B3 > B1 > A | |
2 | B3 > B1 > B2 > A | |
1 | A > B3 > B1 > B2 |
Since all preferences are strict rankings (no equals are present), all three minimax methods (winning votes, margins and pairwise opposite) elect the same winners.
Assume only one of the clones would compete. The preferences would be:
| Preferences | |
---|---|---|
4 | A > B1 | |
5 | B1 > A |
The results would be tabulated as follows:
X | |||
A | B1 | ||
Y | A | [X] 5 [Y] 4 | |
B1 | [X] 4 [Y] 5 | ||
Pairwise election results (won-tied-lost): | 0-1 | 1-0 | |
worst pairwise defeat (winning votes): | 5 | 0 | |
worst pairwise defeat (margins): | 1 | 0 | |
worst pairwise opposition: | 5 | 4 |
Result: B is the Condorcet winner. Thus, B is elected minimax winner.
Now assume all three clones would compete. The preferences would be as follows:
| Preferences | |
---|---|---|
3 | A > B1 > B2 > B3 | |
3 | B2 > B3 > B1 > A | |
2 | B3 > B1 > B2 > A | |
1 | A > B3 > B1 > B2 |
The results would be tabulated as follows:
X | |||||
A | B1 | B2 | B3 | ||
Y | A | [X] 5 [Y] 4 | [X] 5 [Y] 4 | [X] 5 [Y] 4 | |
B1 | [X] 4 [Y] 5 | [X] 3 [Y] 6 | [X] 6 [Y] 3 | ||
B2 | [X] 4 [Y] 5 | [X] 6 [Y] 3 | [X] 3 [Y] 6 | ||
B3 | [X] 4 [Y] 5 | [X] 3 [Y] 6 | [X] 6 [Y] 3 | ||
Pairwise election results (won-tied-lost): | 0-0-3 | 2-0-1 | 2-0-1 | 2-0-1 | |
worst pairwise defeat (winning votes): | 5 | 6 | 6 | 6 | |
worst pairwise defeat (margins): | 1 | 3 | 3 | 3 | |
worst pairwise opposition: | 5 | 6 | 6 | 6 |
Result: A has the closest biggest defeat. Thus, A is elected minimax winner.
By adding clones, the Condorcet winner B1 becomes defeated. All three clones beat each other in clear defeats. A benefits from that. So, by adding two clones of B, B changed from winner to loser. Thus, the minimax method is vulnerable against spoilers and fails the independence of clones criterion.
STAR voting consists of an automatic runoff between the two candidates with the highest rated scores. This example involves clones with nearly identical scores, and shows teaming.
Scores | ||||
---|---|---|---|---|
| Amy | Brian | Clancy | |
2 | 5 | 2 | 1 | |
4 | 4 | 2 | 1 | |
11 | 0 | 1 | 1 |
The finalists are Amy and Brian, and Brian beats Amy pairwise and thus wins.[4]
Scores | |||||
---|---|---|---|---|---|
| Amy | Amy's clone | Brian | Clancy | |
2 | 5 | 5 | 2 | 1 | |
2 | 4 | 3 | 2 | 1 | |
2 | 4 | 5 | 2 | 1 | |
11 | 0 | 0 | 1 | 1 |
The finalists are Amy and her clone, and Amy's clone wins.[5]