Human germline engineering explained

Human germline engineering is the process by which the genome of an individual is edited in such a way that the change is heritable. This is achieved by altering the genes of the germ cells, which then mature into genetically modified eggs and sperm. For safety, ethical, and social reasons, there is broad agreement among the scientific community and the public that germline editing for reproduction is a red line that should not be crossed at this point in time. There are differing public sentiments, however, on whether it may be performed in the future depending on whether the intent would be therapeutic or non-therapeutic.[1] [2]

Using germline editing for reproduction is prohibited by law in more than 70 countries[3] and by a binding international treaty of the Council of Europe. However, in November 2015, a group of Chinese scientists used the gene-editing technique CRISPR/Cas9 to edit single-celled, non-viable embryos to see the effectiveness of this technique. This attempt was rather unsuccessful; only a small fraction of the embryos successfully incorporated the new genetic material and many of the embryos contained a large number of random mutations. The non-viable embryos that were used contained an extra set of chromosomes, which may have been problematic. In 2016, another similar study was performed in China which also used non-viable embryos with extra sets of chromosomes. This study showed very similar results to the first; but there weren't successful integrations of the desired gene, and the majority of the attempts failed, or produced undesirable mutations.

In November 2018, researcher He Jiankui created the first human genetically edited babies, known by their pseudonyms, Lulu and Nana. In May 2019, lawyers in China reported, in light of the purported creation by He Jiankui of the first gene-edited humans, the drafting of regulations that anyone manipulating the human genome by gene-editing techniques, like CRISPR, would be held responsible for any related adverse consequences.[4]

Techniques

CRISPR-Cas9

See main article: CRISPR and Cas9. In general, CRISPR-Cas9 is one of the most effective gene-editing technique to date. The CRISPR-Cas9 system consists of an enzyme called Cas9 and a special piece of guide RNA (gRNA). Cas9 acts as a pair of ‘molecular scissors’ that can cut the DNA at a specific location in the genome so that DNA can be added or removed. The guide RNA is a piece of RNA with complementary bases to those at the target location, so that it will only bind there and no other regions of the genome. The Cas9 follows the guide RNA to the same location in the DNA sequence and makes a cut across both strands of the DNA. At this stage, the cell recognizes that the DNA is damaged and tries to repair it.[5] Scientists can use the DNA repair machinery to introduce changes to one or more genes in the genome of a cell of interest.

Although the CRISPR/Cas9 can be used in humans,[6] it is more commonly used by scientists in other animal models or cell culture systems, including in experiments to learn more about genes that could be involved in human diseases. Clinical trials are being conducted on somatic cells, but CRISPR could make it possible to modify the DNA of spermatogonial stem cells. This could be used to eliminate certain diseases in humans, or at least significantly decrease a disease's frequency until it eventually disappears over generations.[7] Cancer survivors theoretically would be able to have their genes modified by the CRISPR/Cas9 so that certain diseases or mutations will not be passed down to their offspring. This could possibly eliminate cancer predispositions in humans. Researchers hope that they can use the system in the future to treat currently incurable diseases by altering the genome altogether.

Conceivable uses

Human germline engineering could be used to heritably cure genetic disorders and other diseases, and to give specific traits to human babies. For example, The Berlin Patient has a genetic mutation in the CCR5 gene (which codes for a protein on the surface of white blood cells, targeted by the HIV virus) that deactivates the expression of CCR5, conferring innate resistance to HIV. HIV/AIDS carries a large disease burden and is incurable (see Epidemiology of HIV/AIDS). One proposal is to genetically modify human embryos to give the CCR5 Δ32 allele to people.

Another use would be to cure genetic disorders. In the first study published regarding human germline engineering, the researchers attempted to edit the HBB gene which codes for the human β-globin protein.[8] Mutations in the HBB gene result in the disorder β-thalassaemia, which can be fatal. Perfect editing of the genome in patients who have these HBB mutations would result in copies of the gene which do not possess any mutations, effectively curing the disease. If the germline could be edited, this normal copy of the HBB genes could be passed on to future generations.

Designer babies

See main article: articles and Designer baby. The non-therapeutic use of human germline engineering would be eugenic modifications to humans which would result in what are known as "designer babies". The concept of a "designer baby" is that its entire genetic composition could be selected for.[9] In an extreme case, people would be able to effectively create the offspring that they want, with a genotype of their choosing. Not only does human germline engineering allow for the selection of specific traits, but it also allows for enhancement of these traits. Using human germline editing for selection and enhancement is currently very heavily scrutinized, and the main driving force behind the movement of trying to ban human germline engineering.[10]

In a 2019 animal study with Liang Guang Small Spotted pigs, increased muscle mass was achieved with precise editing of the myostatin signal peptide. Myostatin is a negative regulator of muscle growth, so through mutating the signal peptide regions of the gene, muscle growth could be promoted in the experimental pigs. The Myostatin genes in 955 pig embryos were mutated at several locations with CRISPR and implanted into five surrogates, resulting in 16 piglets. It was found that only specific mutations to the myostatin signal peptide resulted in increased muscle mass in the piglets mainly due to an increase in muscle fibers.[11] A similar animal study created a knockout in the myostatin gene in mice, which also increased their muscle mass.[12] This showed that muscle mass could be increased with germline editing, which is likely applicable to humans because humans also have the myostatin gene to regulate muscle growth.[13] Human germline engineering may then result in intentionally increased muscle mass, with applications such as gene doping.

State of research

Human germline engineering is a widely debated topic, and in more than 40 countries, it is formally outlawed.[14] While there is no current legislation explicitly prohibiting germline engineering in the United States, the Consolidated Appropriation Act of 2016 bans the use of US FDA funds to engage in research regarding human germline modification.[15] In April 2015, a research team published an experiment in which they used CRISPR to edit a gene that is associated with blood disease in non-living human embryos. This experiment was unsuccessful, but gene editing tools are used in labs.

Scientists using the CRISPR/Cas9 system to modify genetic materials have run into issues when it comes to mammalian alterations due to the complex diploid cells. Studies have been done in microorganisms regarding loss of function genetic screening and some studies have been done using mice as a subject. Because RNA processes differ between bacteria and mammalian cells, scientists have had difficulties coding for mRNA's translated data without the interference of RNA. Studies have been done using the Cas9 nuclease that uses a single guide RNA to allow for larger knockout regions in mice, and this was successful.[16] Altering the genetic sequence of mammals is also widely debated, and this creates a difficult FDA regulation standard for such studies.

Lack of clear international regulation

The lack of clear international regulation has led to researchers across the globe attempting to create an international framework of ethical guidelines. Current framework lacks the requisite treaties among nations to create a mechanism for international enforcement. At the first International Summit on Human Gene Editing in December 2015 the collaboration of scientists issued the first international guidelines on genetic research.[17] These guidelines allow for the pre-clinical research into the editing of genetic sequences in human cells granted the embryos are not used to implant pregnancy. Genetic alteration of somatic cells for therapeutic proposes was also considered an ethically acceptable field of research in part due to the lack of ability of somatic cells to transfer genetic material to subsequent generations. However citing the lack of social consensus, and the risk of inaccurate gene editing the conference called for restraint on any germline modifications on implanted embryos intended for pregnancy.

With the international outcry in response to the first recorded case of human germ line edited embryos being implanted by researcher He Jiankui, scientists have continued discussion on the best possible mechanism for enforcement of an international framework. On March 13, 2019 researchers Eric Lander, Françoise Baylis, Feng Zhang, Emmanuelle Charpentier, Paul Bergfrom along with others across the globe published a call for a framework that does not foreclose any outcome but includes a voluntary pledge by nations along with a coordinating body to monitor the application of pledged nations in a moratorium on human germline editing with an attempt to reach social consensus before moving forward into further research.[18] The World Health Organization announced on December 18, 2018 plans to convene an intentional committee on clinical germline editing.[19]

He Jiankui controversy and research

See main article: He Jiankui affair. On 25 November 2018, two days before the Second International Summit on Human Genome Editing in Hong Kong, He Jiankui, a Chinese researcher of the Southern University of Science and Technology, released a video on YouTube announcing that he and his colleagues have “created” the world's first genetically altered babies, Lulu and Nana.

He explained the details of his experiment in his address at the Hong Kong conference. He and his team had recruited eight couples through an HIV volunteer group named Baihualin (BHL) China League (one couple later withdrew from the research). All the male participants are HIV-positive, and all female participants are HIV-negative. The participants' sperm was “washed off” to get rid of HIV and then injected into eggs collected from the female participants. By using clustered regularly interspaced short palindromic repeat (CRISPR)-Cas9, a gene editing technique, they disabled a gene called CCR5 in the embryos, aiming to close the protein doorway that allows HIV to enter a cell and make the subjects immune to the HIV virus. The process led to at least one successful pregnancy and the birth of the twin baby girls, Lulu and Nana.[20] [21] Researcher Alcino J. Silva has discovered an impact the CCR5 gene has on the memory function the brain.[22]

A major concern has been that He Jiankui's attempts to cripple CCR5, the gene for a protein on immune cells that HIV uses to infect the cells, also made “off-target” changes elsewhere in the girls' genomes. Those changes could cause cancer or other problems. He contends that the babies have no such off-target mutations, although some scientists are skeptical of the evidence offered so far.[23]

People inherit two copies of CCR5, one from each parent. He chose the gene as a target because he knew that about 1% of Northern European populations are born with both copies missing 32 base pairs, resulting in a truncated protein that does not reach the cell surface. These people, known as CCR5Δ32 homozygotes, appear healthy and are highly resistant to HIV infection.

In the embryos, He's team designed CRISPR to cut CCR5 at the base pair at one end of the natural deletion. The error-prone cell-repair mechanism, which CRISPR depends on to finish knocking out genes, then deleted 15 base pairs in one of Lulu's copies of the gene, but none in the other. With one normal CCR5, she is expected to have no protection from HIV. Nana, according to the data He presented in a slide at an international genome-editing summit held in November 2018 in Hong Kong, China, had bases added to one CCR5 copy and deleted from the other, which likely would cripple both genes and provide HIV resistance.

He added the genes for the CRISPR machinery almost immediately after each embryo was created through in vitro fertilization, but several researchers who closely studied the slide caution that it may have done its editing after Nana's embryo was already past the one-cell stage. That means she could be a genetic “mosaic” who has some unaffected cells with normal CCR5—and ultimately might have no protection from HIV.

Aside from the primary HIV concerns, the gene edits may have inadvertently altered cognitive function. Researchers showed in 2016 that knocking out one or both CCR5s in mice enhances their memory and cognition. A subsequent study that crippled CCR5 in mice found that, compared with control animals, the mutants recovered from strokes more quickly and had improved motor and cognitive functions following traumatic brain injury. The later study, in the 21 February issue of Cell, also included an analysis of 68 stroke patients who had one copy of CCR5 with the HIV resistance mutation; it concluded they had improved recovery, too.

On the night of November 26, 122 Chinese scientists issued a statement strongly condemning He's action as unethical. They stated that while CRISPR-Cas is not a new technology, it involves serious off-target risks and associated ethical considerations, and so should not be used to produce gene-altered babies. They described He's experiment as “crazy” and “a huge blow to the global reputation and development of Chinese science”. The Scientific Ethics Committee of the Academic Divisions of the Chinese Academy of Sciences posted a statement declaring their opposition to any clinical use of genome editing on human embryos, noting that “the theory is not reliable, the technology is deficient, the risks are uncontrollable, and ethics and regulations prohibit the action”.[24] The Chinese Academy of Engineering released a statement on November 28, calling on scientists to improve self-discipline and self-regulation, and to abide by corresponding ethical principles, laws, and regulations. Finally, the Chinese Academy of Medical Sciences published a correspondence in The Lancet, stating that they are “opposed to any clinical operation of human embryo genome editing for reproductive purposes."

Major studies of influence

Ethical and moral debates

As early in the history of biotechnology as 1990, there have been scientists opposed to attempts to modify the human germline using these new tools,[29] and such concerns have continued as technology progressed.[30] [31] In March 2015, with the advent of new techniques like CRISPR, a group of scientists urged a worldwide moratorium on clinical use of gene editing technologies to edit the human genome in a way that can be inherited.[32] In April 2015, researchers reported results of basic research to edit the DNA of non-viable human embryos using CRISPR, creating controversy.[33]

A committee of the American National Academy of Sciences and National Academy of Medicine gave support to human genome editing in 2017[34] [35] once answers have been found to safety and efficiency problems "but only for serious conditions under stringent oversight."[36] The American Medical Association's Council on Ethical and Judicial Affairs stated that "genetic interventions to enhance traits should be considered permissible only in severely restricted situations: (1) clear and meaningful benefits to the fetus or child; (2) no trade-off with other characteristics or traits; and (3) equal access to the genetic technology, irrespective of income or other socioeconomic characteristics."[37]

Several religious positions have been published with regards to human germline engineering. According to them, many see germline modification as being more moral than the alternative, which would be either discarding of the embryo, or birth of a diseased human. The main conditions when it comes to whether or not it is morally and ethically acceptable lie within the intent of the modification, and the conditions in which the engineering is done.[38]

Ethical claims about germline engineering include beliefs that every fetus has a right to remain genetically unmodified, that parents hold the right to genetically modify their offspring, and that every child has the right to be born free of preventable diseases.[39] [40] [41] For parents, genetic engineering could be seen as another child enhancement technique to add to diet, exercise, education, training, cosmetics, and plastic surgery.[42] [43] Another theorist claims that moral concerns limit but do not prohibit germline engineering.[44]

Consent

One issue related to human genome editing relates to the impact of the technology on future individuals whose genes are modified without their consent. Clinical ethics accepts the idea that parents are, almost always, the most appropriate surrogate medical decision makers for their children until the children develop their own autonomy and decision-making capacity. This is based on the assumption that, except under rare circumstances, parents have the most to lose or gain from a decision and will ultimately make decisions that reflects the future values and beliefs of their children. According to this assumption, it could be assumed that parents are the most appropriate decision makers for their future children as well. However, there are anecdotal reports of children and adults who disagree with the medical decisions made by a parent during pregnancy or early childhood, such as when death was a possible outcome. There are also published patient stories by individuals who feel that they would not wish to change or remove their own medical condition if given the choice and individuals who disagree with medical decisions made by their parents during childhood.[45]

Other scientists and philosophers have noted that the issue of the lack of prior consent applies as well to individuals born via traditional sexual reproduction.[46] [47] Philosopher David Pearce further argues that “old-fashioned sexual reproduction is itself an untested genetic experiment”, often compromising a child's wellbeing and pro-social capacities even if the child grows in a healthy environment. According to Pearce, “the question of [human germline engineering] comes down to an analysis of risk-reward ratios – and our basic ethical values, themselves shaped by our evolutionary past.”[48] Bioethicist Julian Savulescu in turn proposes the principle of procreative beneficence, according to which “couples (or single reproducers) should select the child, of the possible children they could have, who is expected to have the best life, or at least as good a life as the others, based on the relevant, available information”.[49] Some ethicists argue that the principle of procreative beneficence would justify or even require genetically enhancing one's children.[50] [51]

A relevant issue concerns “off target effects”, large genomes may contain identical or homologous DNA sequences, and the enzyme complex CRISPR/Cas9 may unintentionally cleave these DNA sequences causing mutations that may lead to cell death. The mutations can cause important genes to be turned on or off, such as genetic anti-cancer mechanisms, that could speed up disease exasperation.[52] [53] [54] [55]

Unequal distribution of benefits

The other ethical concern is the potential for “designer babies”, or the creation of humans with "perfect", or "desirable" traits. There is a debate as to if this is morally acceptable as well. Such debate ranges from the ethical obligation to use safe and efficient technology to prevent disease to seeing some actual benefit in genetic disabilities.

There are concerns that the introduction of desirable traits in a certain part of the population (instead of the entire population) could cause economic inequalities (“positional” good).[56] However, this is not the case if a same desirable trait would be introduced over the entire population (similar to vaccines).

Another ethical concern pertains to potential unequal distribution of benefits, even in the case of genome editing being inexpensive. For example, corporations may be able to take unfair advantage of patent law or other ways of restricting access to genome editing and thereby may increase the inequalities. There are already disputes in the courts where CRISPR-Cas9 patents and access issues are being negotiated.[57]

Therapeutic and non-therapeutic use

There remains debate on if the permissibility of human germline engineering for reproduction is dependent on the use, being either a therapeutic or non-therapeutic application. In a survey by the UK's Royal Society, 76% of participants in the UK supported therapeutic human germline engineering to prevent or correct disease, however for non-therapeutic edits such as enhancing intelligence or altering eye or hair color in embryos, there was only 40% and 31% support, respectively. There was a similar result in a study at the University of Bogota, Colombia, where students as well as professors generally agreed that therapeutic genome editing is acceptable, while non-therapeutic genome editing is not.

There is also debate on if there can be a defined distinction between therapeutic and non-therapeutic germline editing. An example would be if two embryos are predicted to grow up to be very short in height. Boy 1 will be short because of a mutation in his Human Growth Hormone gene, while boy 2 will be short because his parents are very short. Editing the embryo of boy 1 to make him of average height would be a therapeutic germline edit, while editing the embryo of boy 2 to be of average height would be a non-therapeutic germline edit. In both cases with no editing of the boys' genomes they would both grow up to be very short, which would decrease their wellbeing in life. Likewise editing both of the boys' genomes would allow them to grow up to be of average height. In this scenario, editing for the same phenotype for being of average height falls under both therapeutic and non-therapeutic germline engineering.[58]

Current global policy

There is distinction in some country policies, including but not limited to official regulation and legislation, between human germline engineering for reproductive use and for laboratory research. As of October 2020, there are 96 countries that have policies involving the use of germline engineering in human cells.

Reproductive use

Reproductive use of human germline engineering involves implanting the edited embryo to be born. 70 countries currently explicitly prohibit the use of human germline engineering for use in reproduction, while 5 countries prohibit it for reproduction with exceptions. No countries permit the use of human germline engineering for reproduction.

Countries that explicitly prohibit any use of human germline engineering for reproduction are: Albania, Argentina, Australia, Austria, Bahrain, Belarus, Benin, Bosnia and Herzegovina, Brazil, Bulgaria, Burundi, Canada, Chile, China, Congo, Costa Rica, Croatia, Cyprus, Czech Republic, Denmark, Estonia, Finland, France, Georgia, Germany, Greece, Hungary, Iceland, India, Iran, Ireland, Israel, Japan, Kenya, Latvia, Lebanon, Lithuania, Malaysia, Malta, Mexico, Moldova, Montenegro, Netherlands, New Zealand, Nigeria, North Macedonia, Norway, Oman, Pakistan, Poland, Portugal, Qatar, Romania, Russia, San Marino, Saudi Arabia, Serbia, Slovakia, Slovenia, South Korea, Spain, Sweden, Switzerland, Thailand, Tunisia, Turkey, the United Kingdom, the United States, Uruguay, and the Vatican

Countries that explicitly prohibit (with exceptions) the use of human germline engineering for reproduction are: Belgium, Colombia, Italy, Panama, and the United Arab Emirates

Laboratory research

Laboratory research use involves human germline engineering restricted to in vitro use, where edited cells will not be implanted to be born. 19 countries currently explicitly prohibit any use of human germline engineering for in vitro use, while 4 prohibit it with exceptions, and 11 permit it.

Countries that explicitly prohibit any use of germline engineering for in vitro use are: Albania, Austria, Bahrain, Belarus, Brazil, Canada, Costa Rica, Croatia, Germany, Greece, Lebanon, Malaysia, Malta, Pakistan, Saudi Arabia, Sweden, Switzerland, Uruguay, and the Vatican

Countries that explicitly prohibit (with exceptions) the use of germline engineering for in vitro use are: Colombia, Finland, Italy, and Panama

Countries that explicitly permit the use of germline engineering for in vitro use are: Burundi, China, Congo, India, Iran, Ireland, Japan, Norway, Thailand, the United Kingdom, and the United States

See also

Further reading

Notes and References

  1. McGee . Andrew . 2019-10-15 . Using the therapy and enhancement distinction in law and policy . Bioethics . 34 . 1 . 70–80 . 10.1111/bioe.12662 . 31617223 . 204738693 . 0269-9702.
  2. Caro-Romero . Henry David . 2020-06-09 . Edición genómica heredable: un estudio exploratorio desde la perspectiva del principio bioético de la beneficencia . Revista Colombiana de Bioética . 15 . 1 . 10.18270/rcb.v15i1.2732 . 225804689 . 2590-9452. free .
  3. Baylis . Françoise . Darnovsky . Marcy . Hasson . Katie . Krahn . Timothy M. . 2020-10-01 . Human Germline and Heritable Genome Editing: The Global Policy Landscape . The CRISPR Journal . en . 3 . 5 . 365–377 . 10.1089/crispr.2020.0082 . 2573-1599 . 33095042 . 225053656. free .
  4. Ma H, Marti-Gutierrez N, Park SW, Wu J, Lee Y, Suzuki K, Koski A, Ji D, Hayama T, Ahmed R, Darby H, Van Dyken C, Li Y, Kang E, Park AR, Kim D, Kim ST, Gong J, Gu Y, Xu X, Battaglia D, Krieg SA, Lee DM, Wu DH, Wolf DP, Heitner SB, Belmonte JC, Amato P, Kim JS, Kaul S, Mitalipov S . Correction of a pathogenic gene mutation in human embryos . Nature . 548 . 7668 . 413–419 . August 2017 . 28783728 . 10.1038/nature23305 . 2017Natur.548..413M . free .
  5. Ormond KE, Mortlock DP, Scholes DT, Bombard Y, Brody LC, Faucett WA, Garrison NA, Hercher L, Isasi R, Middleton A, Musunuru K, Shriner D, Virani A, Young CE . 6 . Human Germline Genome Editing . American Journal of Human Genetics . 101 . 2 . 167–176 . August 2017 . 28777929 . 5544380 . 10.1016/j.ajhg.2017.06.012 .
  6. Rodríguez-Rodríguez. Diana Raquel. Ramírez-Solís. Ramiro. Garza-Elizondo. Mario Alberto. Garza-Rodríguez. María De Lourdes. Barrera-Saldaña. Hugo Alberto. April 2019. Genome editing: A perspective on the application of CRISPR/Cas9 to study human diseases (Review). International Journal of Molecular Medicine. 43. 4. 1559–1574. 10.3892/ijmm.2019.4112. 1791-244X. 6414166. 30816503.
  7. Katz G, Pitts PJ . Implications of CRISPR-Based Germline Engineering for Cancer Survivors . Therapeutic Innovation & Regulatory Science . 51 . 6 . 672–682 . November 2017 . 30227096 . 10.1177/2168479017723401 . 13658866 .
  8. Cyranoski . David . Reardon . Sara . 22 April 2015 . Chinese scientists genetically modify human embryos . Nature . nature.2015.17378 . 10.1038/nature.2015.17378 . 87604469.
  9. National Academies of Sciences, Engineering, and Medicine. 2017. Human Genome Editing: Science, Ethics, and Governance. Washington, DC: The National Academies Press. doi: 10.17226/24623.
  10. Book: New Horizons in Medical Anthropology: Essays in Honour of Charles Leslie. Lock. Margaret. Nichter. Mark . vanc . 2003-09-02. Routledge. 9781134471287.
  11. Li . Ruiqiang . Zeng . Wu . Ma . Miao . Wei . Zixuan . Liu . Hongbo . Liu . Xiaofeng . Wang . Min . Shi . Xuan . Zeng . Jianhua . Yang . Linfang . Mo . Delin . Liu . Xiaohong . Chen . Yaosheng . He . Zuyong . February 2020 . Precise editing of myostatin signal peptide by CRISPR/Cas9 increases the muscle mass of Liang Guang Small Spotted pigs . Transgenic Research . en . 29 . 1 . 149–163 . 10.1007/s11248-020-00188-w . 31927726 . 255111445 . 0962-8819.
  12. Professor . Apostolos Stergioulas, Ph D. . Gene doping in modern sport . 2021-02-04 . 2022-12-06 . Journal Biology of Exercise . 5 . en-US . 10.4127/jbe.2009.0021.
  13. Gonzalez-Cadavid . Nestor F. . Taylor . Wayne E. . Yarasheski . Kevin . Sinha-Hikim . Indrani . Ma . Kun . Ezzat . Shereen . Shen . Ruoqing . Lalani . Rukhsana . Asa . Sylvia . Mamita . Mohamad . Nair . Gouri . Arver . Stefan . Bhasin . Shalender . 1998-12-08 . Organization of the human myostatin gene and expression in healthy men and HIV-infected men with muscle wasting . Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences . en . 95 . 25 . 14938–14943 . 10.1073/pnas.95.25.14938 . 0027-8424 . 24554 . 9843994. free .
  14. Lanphier E, Urnov F, Haecker SE, Werner M, Smolenski J . March 2015 . Don't edit the human germ line . Nature . 519 . 7544 . 410–1 . 2015Natur.519..410L . 10.1038/519410a . 25810189 . free.
  15. Cohen IG, Adashi EY . SCIENCE AND REGULATION. The FDA is prohibited from going germline . Science . 353 . 6299 . 545–6 . August 2016 . 27493171 . 10.1126/science.aag2960 . 2016Sci...353..545C . 206651381 .
  16. Wang . Tim . etal . 2014 . Genetic screens in human cells using the CRISPR-Cas9 system . Science . 343 . 6166. 80–4 . 10.1126/science.1246981 . 2014Sci...343...80W . 3972032 . 24336569 .
  17. Web site: On Human Gene Editing: International Summit Statement. www8.nationalacademies.org. 2019-04-18.
  18. Germline gene-editing research needs rules . Nature . 567 . 7747 . 145 . March 2019 . 30867612 . 10.1038/d41586-019-00788-5 . 2019Natur.567..145. . free .
  19. Web site: WHO Gene editing. https://web.archive.org/web/20190222155933/https://www.who.int/ethics/topics/human-genome-editing/en/. dead. February 22, 2019. WHO. 2019-04-18.
  20. News: Begley . Sharon . 28 November 2018 . Amid uproar, Chinese scientist defends creating gene-edited babies . STAT News .
  21. Web site: 27 November 2018 . 复盘贺建奎的人生轨迹:是谁给了他勇气 . 28 November 2018 . . zh.
  22. Web site: 2019-01-21 . He Jiankui Fired in Wake of CRISPR Babies Investigation . 2019-04-18 . GEN - Genetic Engineering and Biotechnology News.
  23. Web site: 2018-11-28 . Amid uproar, Chinese scientist defends creating gene-edited babies . 2019-04-18 . STAT.
  24. Liang P, Xu Y, Zhang X, Ding C, Huang R, Zhang Z, Lv J, Xie X, Chen Y, Li Y, Sun Y, Bai Y, Songyang Z, Ma W, Zhou C, Huang J . May 2015 . CRISPR/Cas9-mediated gene editing in human tripronuclear zygotes . Protein & Cell . 6 . 5 . 363–372 . 10.1007/s13238-015-0153-5 . 4417674 . 25894090.
  25. Tang L, Zeng Y, Du H, Gong M, Peng J, Zhang B, Lei M, Zhao F, Wang W, Li X, Liu J . June 2017 . CRISPR/Cas9-mediated gene editing in human zygotes using Cas9 protein . Molecular Genetics and Genomics . 292 . 3 . 525–533 . 10.1007/s00438-017-1299-z . 28251317 . 16358211.
  26. 6 . Ma H, Marti-Gutierrez N, Park SW, Wu J, Lee Y, Suzuki K, Koski A, Ji D, Hayama T, Ahmed R, Darby H, Van Dyken C, Li Y, Kang E, Park AR, Kim D, Kim ST, Gong J, Gu Y, Xu X, Battaglia D, Krieg SA, Lee DM, Wu DH, Wolf DP, Heitner SB, Belmonte JC, Amato P, Kim JS, Kaul S, Mitalipov S . August 2017 . Correction of a pathogenic gene mutation in human embryos . Nature . 548 . 7668 . 413–419 . 2017Natur.548..413M . 10.1038/nature23305 . 28783728 . free.
  27. Haapaniemi E, Botla S, Persson J, Schmierer B, Taipale J . July 2018 . CRISPR-Cas9 genome editing induces a p53-mediated DNA damage response . Nature Medicine . 24 . 7 . 927–930 . 10.1038/s41591-018-0049-z . 29892067 . 47018050 . free . 10138/303675.
  28. Zeng Y, Li J, Li G, Huang S, Yu W, Zhang Y, Chen D, Chen J, Liu J, Huang X . November 2018 . Correction of the Marfan Syndrome Pathogenic FBN1 Mutation by Base Editing in Human Cells and Heterozygous Embryos . Molecular Therapy . en . 26 . 11 . 2631–2637 . 10.1016/j.ymthe.2018.08.007 . 6224777 . 30166242.
  29. https://web.archive.org/web/20010805085535/http://www.cioms.ch/frame_1990_texts_of_guidelines.htm The Declaration of Inuyama: Human Genome Mapping, Genetic Screening and Gene Therapy
  30. Smith KR, Chan S, Harris J . Human germline genetic modification: scientific and bioethical perspectives . Archives of Medical Research . 43 . 7 . 491–513 . October 2012 . 23072719 . 10.1016/j.arcmed.2012.09.003 .
  31. Reardon . Sara . US science advisers outline path to genetically modified babies . Nature . 14 February 2017 . nature.2017.21474 . 10.1038/nature.2017.21474 . free .
  32. News: Wade . Nicholas . vanc . Scientists Seek Ban on Method of Editing the Human Genome . 19 March 2015 . . 20 March 2015 . The biologists writing in Science support continuing laboratory research with the technique, and few if any scientists believe it is ready for clinical use..
  33. News: Kolata . Gina . vanc . Chinese Scientists Edit Genes of Human Embryos, Raising Concerns . 23 April 2015 . . 24 April 2015 .
  34. News: Human Gene Editing Receives Science Panel's Support. Harmon. Amy. vanc . 2017-02-14. The New York Times. 2017-02-17. 0362-4331.
  35. Web site: Committee on Human Gene Editing: Scientific, Medical, and Ethical Considerations. Human Genome Editing: Science, Ethics, and Governance. nationalacademies.org. National Academy of Sciences; National Academy of Medicine. 21 February 2017.
  36. Web site: Scientists OK genetically engineering babies. 2017-02-14. New York Post. Reuters. 2017-02-17.
  37. Ethical issues related to prenatal genetic testing. The Council on Ethical and Judicial Affairs, American Medical Association . Archives of Family Medicine . 3 . 7 . 633–642 . July 1994 . 7921302 . 10.1001/archfami.3.7.633 .
  38. Book: Cole-Turner, Ronald . Design and Destiny: Jewish and Christian Perspectives on Human Germline Modification . 2008 . MIT Press . 9780262533010.
  39. Powell R, Buchanan A . Breaking evolution's chains: the prospect of deliberate genetic modification in humans . The Journal of Medicine and Philosophy . 36 . 1 . 6–27 . February 2011 . 21228084 . 10.1093/jmp/jhq057 .
  40. Baylis F, Robert JS . The inevitability of genetic enhancement technologies . Bioethics . 18 . 1 . 1–26 . 2004 . 15168695 . 10.1111/j.1467-8519.2004.00376.x .
  41. Book: Evans, John. vanc . Playing God?: Human Genetic Engineering and the Rationalization of Public Bioethical Debate. 2002. University of Chicago Press . 978-0-226-22262-2 .
  42. http://ethics.missouri.edu/Gene-Therapy.aspx Gene Therapy and Genetic Engineering.
  43. Roco MC, Bainbridge WS . Journal of Nanoparticle Research . 2002 . 4 . 4 . 281–295 . 10.1023/A:1021152023349. Converging Technologies for Improving Human Performance: Integrating From the Nanoscale . 2002JNR.....4..281R . 136290217 .
  44. Allhoff . Fritz . Germ-Line Genetic Enhancement and Rawlsian Primary Goods . Kennedy Institute of Ethics Journal . 2005 . 15 . 1 . 39–56 . 10.1353/ken.2005.0007 . 15881795 . 10.1.1.566.171 . 14432440 .
  45. Ishii T . Potential impact of human mitochondrial replacement on global policy regarding germline gene modification . Reproductive Biomedicine Online . 29 . 2 . 150–5 . August 2014 . 24832374 . 10.1016/j.rbmo.2014.04.001 . free . 2115/56864 . free .
  46. Ranisch . Robert . Germline Genome Editing and the Functions of Consent . The American Journal of Bioethics . 2 December 2017 . 17 . 12 . 27–29 . 10.1080/15265161.2017.1388875 . 29148947 . 10117287 .
  47. Vassena . R. . Heindryckx . B. . Peco . R. . Pennings . G. . Raya . A. . Sermon . K. . Veiga . A. . Genome engineering through CRISPR/Cas9 technology in the human germline and pluripotent stem cells . Human Reproduction Update . June 2016 . 22 . 4 . 411–419 . 10.1093/humupd/dmw005 . 26932460 . free .
  48. Book: Pearce, David. Can Biotechnology Abolish Suffering?. 2017. Vinding. Magnus. The Reproductive Revolution. B075MV9KS2. David Pearce (transhumanist).
  49. Savulescu . Julian . Procreative Beneficence: Why We Should Select the Best Children . Bioethics . October 2001 . 15 . 5–6 . 413–426 . 10.1111/1467-8519.00251 . 12058767 .
  50. Veit. Walter. 2018. Procreative Beneficence and Genetic Enhancement. KRITERION - Journal of Philosophy. 32. 75–92. 10.1515/krt-2018-320105 . 149244361 . https://web.archive.org/web/20211023193825/http://www.kriterion-journal-of-philosophy.org/kriterion/issues/Permanent/Kriterion-veit-01.pdf. October 23, 2021.
  51. Daws . Steven . Procreative Beneficence in the CRISPR World . Voices in Bioethics . 6 October 2017 . 3 . 10.7916/vib.v3i.6031 .
  52. Book: Stock, Gregory. Redesigning Humans: Choosing Our Genes, Changing Our Future. 2003. Houghton Mifflin Harcourt. 978-0618340835.
  53. Wivel . Nelson A. . Walters . LeRoy . Germ-Line Gene Modification and Disease Prevention: Some Medical and Ethical Perspectives . Science . 22 October 1993 . 262 . 5133 . 533–538 . . 10.1126/science.8211180 . 8211180 .
  54. Darnovsky . Marcy . A slippery slope to human germline modification . Nature . July 2013 . 499 . 7457 . 127 . . 10.1038/499127a . 23846625 . 4430248 . free .
  55. Alanis-Lobato . Gregorio . Zohren . Jasmin . McCarthy . Afshan . Fogarty . Norah M. E. . Kubikova . Nada . Hardman . Emily . Greco . Maria . Wells . Dagan . Turner . James M. A. . Niakan . Kathy K. . June 2021 . Frequent loss of heterozygosity in CRISPR-Cas9–edited early human embryos . Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences . en . 118 . 22 . e2004832117 . 10.1073/pnas.2004832117 . 0027-8424 . 8179174 . 34050011. free .
  56. News: Johnson . Tess . 3 December 2019 . Human genetic enhancement might soon be possible – but where do we draw the line? . The Conversation .
  57. Newson . Ainsley . Wrigley . Anthony . 2016 . Being human: The ethics, law, and scientific progress of genome editing . AQ - Australian Quarterly . 87 . 1 . 3–8 . .
  58. Greene . Marsha . Master . Zubin . 2018-09-01 . Ethical Issues of Using CRISPR Technologies for Research on Military Enhancement . Journal of Bioethical Inquiry . en . 15 . 3 . 327–335 . 10.1007/s11673-018-9865-6 . 29968018 . 49640190 . 1872-4353.