Hall's marriage theorem explained

In mathematics, Hall's marriage theorem, proved by, is a theorem with two equivalent formulations. In each case, the theorem gives a necessary and sufficient condition for an object to exist:

Combinatorial formulation

Statement

Let

lF

be a finite family of sets (note that although

lF

is not itself allowed to be infinite, the sets in it may be so, and

lF

may contain the same set multiple times).[1] Let

X

be the union of all the sets in

lF

, the set of elements that belong to at least one of its sets. A transversal for

lF

is a subset of

X

that can be obtained by choosing a distinct element from each set in

lF

. This concept can be formalized by defining a transversal to be the image of an injective function

f:lF\toX

such that

f(S)\inS

for each

S\inlF

. An alternative term for transversal is system of distinct representatives.

The collection

lF

satisfies the marriage condition when each subfamily of

lF

contains at least as many distinct members as its number of sets. That is, for all

lG\subseteqlF

,|\mathcal G|\le\Bigl|\bigcup_ S\Bigr|.If a transversal exists then the marriage condition must be true: the function

f

used to define the transversal maps

lG

to a subset of its union, of size equal to

|lG|

, so the whole union must be at least as large. Hall's theorem states that the converse is also true:

Examples

Example 1
  • Consider the family

    lF=\{A1,A2,A3\}

    with

    X=\{1,2,3,4,5\}

    and \beginA_1&=\\\A_2&=\\\A_3&=\.\\\end The transversal

    \{1,3,5\}

    could be generated by the function that maps

    A1

    to

    1

    ,

    A2

    to

    5

    , and

    A3

    to

    3

    , or alternatively by the function that maps

    A1

    to

    3

    ,

    A2

    to

    1

    , and

    A3

    to

    5

    . There are other transversals, such as

    \{1,2,3\}

    and

    \{1,4,5\}

    . Because this family has at least one transversal, the marriage condition is met. Every subfamily of

    lF

    has equal size to the set of representatives it is mapped to, which is less than or equal to the size of the union of the subfamily.
    Example 2
  • Consider

    lF=\{A1,A2,A3,A4\}

    with \beginA_1&=\\\A_2&=\\\A_3&=\\\A_4&=\.\\\end No valid transversal exists; the marriage condition is violated as is shown by the subfamily

    lG=\{A2,A3,A4\}

    . Here the number of sets in the subfamily is

    |lG|=3

    , while the union of the three sets

    A2\cupA3\cupA4=\{4,5\}

    contains only two elements.

    A lower bound on the different number of transversals that a given finite family

    lF

    of size

    n

    may have is obtained as follows: If each of the sets in

    lF

    has cardinality

    \geqr

    , then the number of different transversals for

    lF

    is either

    r!

    if

    r\leqn

    , or

    r(r-1)(r-n+1)

    if

    r>n

    .[2]

    Recall that a transversal for a family

    lF

    is an ordered sequence, so two different transversals could have exactly the same elements. For instance, the collection

    A1=\{1,2,3\}

    ,

    A2=\{1,2,5\}

    has

    (1,2)

    and

    (2,1)

    as distinct transversals.

    Graph theoretic formulation

    Let

    G=(X,Y,E)

    be a finite bipartite graph with bipartite sets

    X

    and

    Y

    and edge set

    E

    . An

    X

    -perfect matching
    (also called an

    X

    -saturating matching
    ) is a matching, a set of disjoint edges, which covers every vertex in

    X

    .

    For a subset

    W

    of

    X

    , let

    NG(W)

    denote the neighborhood of

    W

    in

    G

    , the set of all vertices in

    Y

    that are adjacent to at least one element of

    W

    . The marriage theorem in this formulation states that there is an

    X

    -perfect matching if and only if for every subset

    W

    of

    X

    : |W| \leq |N_G(W)|. In other words, every subset

    W

    of

    X

    must have sufficiently many neighbors in

    Y

    .

    Proof

    Necessity

    In an

    X

    -perfect matching

    M

    , every edge incident to

    W

    connects to a distinct neighbor of

    W

    in

    Y

    , so the number of these matched neighbors is at least

    |W|

    . The number of all neighbors of

    W

    is at least as large.

    Sufficiency

    Consider the contrapositive: if there is no

    X

    -perfect matching then Hall's condition must be violated for at least one

    W\subseteqX

    . Let

    M

    be a maximum matching, and let

    u

    be any unmatched vertex in

    X

    . Consider all alternating paths (paths in

    G

    that alternately use edges outside and inside

    M

    ) starting from

    u

    . Let

    W

    be the set of vertices in these paths that belong to

    X

    (including

    u

    itself) and let

    Z

    be the set of vertices in these paths that belong to

    Y

    . Then every vertex in

    Z

    is matched by

    M

    to a vertex in

    W

    , because an alternating path to an unmatched vertex could be used to increase the size of the matching by toggling whether each of its edges belongs to

    M

    or not. Therefore, the size of

    W

    is at least the number

    |Z|

    of these matched neighbors of

    Z

    , plus one for the unmatched vertex

    u

    . That is,

    |W|\ge|Z|+1

    . However, for every vertex

    v\inW

    , every neighbor

    w

    of

    v

    belongs to

    Z

    : an alternating path to

    w

    can be found either by removing the matched edge

    vw

    from the alternating path to

    v

    , or by adding the unmatched edge

    vw

    to the alternating path to

    v

    . Therefore,

    Z=NG(W)

    and

    |W|\ge|NG(W)|+1

    , showing that Hall's condition is violated.

    Equivalence of the combinatorial formulation and the graph-theoretic formulation

    A problem in the combinatorial formulation, defined by a finite family of finite sets

    lF

    with union

    X

    can be translated into a bipartite graph

    G=(lF,X,E)

    where each edge connects a set in

    lF

    to an element of that set. An

    lF

    -perfect matching in this graph defines a system of unique representatives for

    lF

    . In the other direction, from any bipartite graph

    G=(X,Y,E)

    one can define a finite family of sets, the family of neighborhoods of the vertices in

    X

    , such that any system of unique representatives for this family corresponds to an

    X

    -perfect matching in

    G

    . In this way, the combinatorial formulation for finite families of finite sets and the graph-theoretic formulation for finite graphs are equivalent.

    The same equivalence extends to infinite families of finite sets and to certain infinite graphs. In this case, the condition that each set be finite corresponds to a condition that in the bipartite graph

    G=(X,Y,E)

    , every vertex in

    X

    should have finite degree. The degrees of the vertices in

    Y

    are not constrained.

    Topological proof

    Hall's theorem can be proved (non-constructively) based on Sperner's lemma.[3]

    Applications

    The theorem has many applications. For example, for a standard deck of cards, dealt into 13 piles of 4 cards each, the marriage theorem implies that it is possible to select one card from each pile so that the selected cards contain exactly one card of each rank (Ace, 2, 3, ..., Queen, King). This can be done by constructing a bipartite graph with one partition containing the 13 piles and the other partition containing the 13 ranks. The remaining proof follows from the marriage condition. More generally, any regular bipartite graph has a perfect matching.[4]

    More abstractly, let

    G

    be a group, and

    H

    be a finite index subgroup of

    G

    . Then the marriage theorem can be used to show that there is a set

    T

    such that

    T

    is a transversal for both the set of left cosets and right cosets of

    H

    in

    G

    .[5]

    The marriage theorem is used in the usual proofs of the fact that an

    r x n

    Latin rectangle can always be extended to an

    (r+1) x n

    Latin rectangle when

    r<n

    , and so, ultimately to a Latin square.[6]

    Logical equivalences

    This theorem is part of a collection of remarkably powerful theorems in combinatorics, all of which are related to each other in an informal sense in that it is more straightforward to prove one of these theorems from another of them than from first principles. These include:

    In particular,[8] there are simple proofs of the implications Dilworth's theorem ⇔ Hall's theorem ⇔ König–Egerváry theorem ⇔ König's theorem.

    Infinite families

    Marshall Hall Jr. variant

    By examining Philip Hall's original proof carefully, Marshall Hall Jr. (no relation to Philip Hall) was able to tweak the result in a way that permitted the proof to work for infinite

    lF

    . This variant extends Philip Hall's Marriage theorem.

    Suppose that

    lF=\{Ai\}i\in

    , is a (possibly infinite) family of finite sets that need not be distinct, then

    lF

    has a transversal if and only if

    lF

    satisfies the marriage condition.

    Marriage condition does not extend

    The following example, due to Marshall Hall Jr., shows that the marriage condition will not guarantee the existence of a transversal in an infinite family in which infinite sets are allowed.

    Let

    lF

    be the family,

    A0=N

    ,

    Ai=\{i-1\}

    for

    i\geq1

    . The marriage condition holds for this infinite family, but no transversal can be constructed.

    Graph theoretic formulation of Marshall Hall's variant

    The graph theoretic formulation of Marshal Hall's extension of the marriage theorem can be stated as follows: Given a bipartite graph with sides A and B, we say that a subset C of B is smaller than or equal in size to a subset D of A in the graph if there exists an injection in the graph (namely, using only edges of the graph) from C to D, and that it is strictly smaller in the graph if in addition there is no injection in the graph in the other direction. Note that omitting in the graph yields the ordinary notion of comparing cardinalities. The infinite marriage theorem states that there exists an injection from A to B in the graph, if and only if there is no subset C of A such that N(C) is strictly smaller than C in the graph.[9]

    The more general problem of selecting a (not necessarily distinct) element from each of a collection of non-empty sets (without restriction as to the number of sets or the size of the sets) is permitted in general only if the axiom of choice is accepted.

    Fractional matching variant

    A fractional matching in a graph is an assignment of non-negative weights to each edge, such that the sum of weights adjacent to each vertex is at most 1. A fractional matching is X-perfect if the sum of weights adjacent to each vertex is exactly 1. The following are equivalent for a bipartite graph G = (X+Y, E):[10]

    Quantitative variant

    See main article: Deficiency (graph theory).

    When Hall's condition does not hold, the original theorem tells us only that a perfect matching does not exist, but does not tell what is the largest matching that does exist. To learn this information, we need the notion of deficiency of a graph. Given a bipartite graph G = (X+Y, E), the deficiency of G w.r.t. X is the maximum, over all subsets W of X, of the difference |W| - |NG(W)|. The larger is the deficiency, the farther is the graph from satisfying Hall's condition.

    Using Hall's marriage theorem, it can be proved that, if the deficiency of a bipartite graph G is d, then G admits a matching of size at least |X|-d.

    Generalizations

    Notes

    1. . An alternative form of the marriage theorem applies to finite families of sets that can be infinite. However, the situation of having an infinite number of sets while allowing infinite sets is not allowed.
    2. , p.90
    3. Haxell. P.. 2011. On Forming Committees. The American Mathematical Monthly. 118. 9. 777–788. 10.4169/amer.math.monthly.118.09.777. 10.4169/amer.math.monthly.118.09.777. 27202372. 0002-9890.
    4. Web site: DeVos . Matt . Graph Theory . Simon Fraser University.
    5. Button. Jack . Maurice . Chiodo. Mariano . Zeron-Medina Laris. Coset Intersection Graphs for Groups. The American Mathematical Monthly. 121. 10. 2014. 922–26. 10.4169/amer.math.monthly.121.10.922. 1304.6111 . 16417209 . For

      H

      a finite index subgroup of

      G

      , the existence of a left-right transversal is well known, sometimes presented as an application of Hall’s marriage theorem..
    6. An existence theorem for latin squares. Marshall. Hall. Bull. Amer. Math. Soc. . 51 . 1945 . 6. 387–388. 10.1090/S0002-9904-1945-08361-X. free.
    7. The naming of this theorem is inconsistent in the literature. There is the result concerning matchings in bipartite graphs and its interpretation as a covering of (0,1)-matrices. and refer to the matrix form as König's theorem, while refer to this version as the Kőnig-Egerváry theorem. The bipartite graph version is called Kőnig's theorem by and .
    8. https://web.archive.org/web/20221027074219/http://www.robertborgersen.info/Presentations/GS-05R-1.pdf Equivalence of seven major theorems in combinatorics
    9. Aharoni. Ron. February 1984. König's Duality Theorem for Infinite Bipartite Graphs. Journal of the London Mathematical Society. s2-29. 1. 1–12. 10.1112/jlms/s2-29.1.1. 0024-6107.
    10. Web site: co.combinatorics - Fractional Matching version of Hall's Marriage theorem. 2020-06-29. MathOverflow.

    External links