Carathéodory's extension theorem explained
In measure theory, Carathéodory's extension theorem (named after the mathematician Constantin Carathéodory) states that any pre-measure defined on a given ring of subsets R of a given set Ω can be extended to a measure on the σ-ring generated by R, and this extension is unique if the pre-measure is σ-finite. Consequently, any pre-measure on a ring containing all intervals of real numbers can be extended to the Borel algebra of the set of real numbers. This is an extremely powerful result of measure theory, and leads, for example, to the Lebesgue measure.
The theorem is also sometimes known as the Carathéodory–Fréchet extension theorem, the Carathéodory–Hopf extension theorem, the Hopf extension theorem and the Hahn–Kolmogorov extension theorem.[1]
Introductory statement
Several very similar statements of the theorem can be given. A slightly more involved one, based on semi-rings of sets, is given further down below. A shorter, simpler statement is as follows. In this form, it is often called the Hahn–Kolmogorov theorem.
Let
be an
algebra of subsets of a
set
Consider a
set function which is
finitely additive, meaning that
for any positive
integer
and
disjoint sets in
Assume that this function satisfies the stronger sigma additivity assumptionfor any disjoint family
of elements of
such that
(Functions
obeying these two properties are known as
pre-measures.) Then,
extends to a measure defined on the
-algebra
generated by
; that is, there exists a measure
such that its
restriction to
coincides with
If
is
-finite, then the extension is unique.
Comments
This theorem is remarkable for it allows one to construct a measure by first defining it on a small algebra of sets, where its sigma additivity could be easy to verify, and then this theorem guarantees its extension to a sigma-algebra. The proof of this theorem is not trivial, since it requires extending
from an algebra of sets to a potentially much bigger sigma-algebra, guaranteeing that the extension is unique (if
is
-finite), and moreover that it does not fail to satisfy the sigma-additivity of the original function.
Semi-ring and ring
Definitions
For a given set
we call a family
of subsets of
a if it has the following properties:
we have
(closed under pairwise intersections)
there exists a finite number of disjoint sets
Ki\inl{S},i=1,2,\ldots,n,
such that
(
relative complements can be written as finite
disjoint unions).
The first property can be replaced with
since
A\inl{S}\impliesA\setminusA=\varnothing\inl{S}.
With the same notation, we call a family
of subsets of
a
if it has the following properties:
we have
(closed under pairwise unions)
we have
(closed under relative complements).
Thus, any ring on
is also a semi-ring.
Sometimes, the following constraint is added in the measure theory context:
is the disjoint union of a
countable family of sets in
A field of sets (respectively, a semi-field) is a ring (respectively, a semi-ring) that also contains
as one of its elements.
Properties
- Arbitrary (possibly uncountable) intersections of rings on
are still rings on
is a non-empty subset of the
powerset
of
then we define the ring generated by
(noted
) as the intersection of all rings containing
It is straightforward to see that the ring generated by
is the smallest ring containing
the set of all finite unions of sets in
is the ring generated by
(One can show that
is equal to the set of all finite disjoint unions of sets in
).
defined on a semi-ring
can be extended on the ring generated by
Such an extension is unique. The extended content can be written:
for
with the
disjoint. In addition, it can be proved that
is a
pre-measure if and only if the extended content is also a pre-measure, and that any pre-measure on
that extends the pre-measure on
is necessarily of this form.
Motivation
In measure theory, we are not interested in semi-rings and rings themselves, but rather in σ-algebras generated by them. The idea is that it is possible to build a pre-measure on a semi-ring
(for example
Stieltjes measures), which can then be extended to a pre-measure on
which can finally be extended to a
measure on a σ-algebra through Caratheodory's extension theorem. As σ-algebras generated by semi-rings and rings are the same, the difference does not really matter (in the measure theory context at least). Actually,
Carathéodory's extension theorem can be slightly generalized by replacing ring by semi-field.
[2] The definition of semi-ring may seem a bit convoluted, but the following example shows why it is useful (moreover it allows us to give an explicit representation of the smallest ring containing some semi-ring).
Example
Think about the subset of
defined by the set of all half-open intervals
for a and b reals. This is a semi-ring, but not a ring.
Stieltjes measures are defined on intervals; the countable additivity on the semi-ring is not too difficult to prove because we only consider countable unions of intervals which are intervals themselves. Proving it for arbitrary countable unions of intervals is accomplished using Caratheodory's theorem.
Statement of the theorem
Let
be a ring of sets on
and let
be a
pre-measure on
meaning that
and for all sets
for which there exists a countable decomposition
in disjoint sets
we have
Let
be the
-algebra generated by
The pre-measure condition is a necessary condition for
to be the restriction to
of a measure on
The Carathéodory's extension theorem states that it is also sufficient,
[3] that is, there exists a measure
\mu\prime:\sigma(R)\to[0,+infty]
such that
is an extension of
that is,
Moreover, if
is
-finite then the extension
is unique (and also
-finite).
[4] Proof sketch
First extend
to an
outer measure
on the
power set
of
by
and then restrict it to the set
of
-measurable sets (that is,
Carathéodory-measurable sets), which is the set of all
such that
\mu*(S)=\mu*(S\capM)+\mu*(S\capMc)
for every
is a
-algebra, and
is
-additive on it, by the Caratheodory lemma.
It remains to check that
contains
That is, to verify that every set in
is
-measurable. This is done by basic measure theory techniques of dividing and adding up sets.
For uniqueness, take any other extension
so it remains to show that
By
-additivity, uniqueness can be reduced to the case where
is finite, which will now be assumed.
Now we could concretely prove
on
by using the
Borel hierarchy of
and since
at the base level, we can use well-ordered induction to reach the level of
the level of
Examples of non-uniqueness of extension
There can be more than one extension of a pre-measure to the generated σ-algebra, if the pre-measure is not
-finite, even if the extensions themselves are
-finite (see example "Via rationals" below).
Via the counting measure
Take the algebra generated by all half-open intervals [''a'',''b'') on the real line, and give such intervals measure infinity if they are non-empty. The Carathéodory extension gives all non-empty sets measure infinity. Another extension is given by the [[counting measure]].
Via rationals
This example is a more detailed variation of the above. The rational closed-open interval is any subset of
of the form
, where
.
Let
be
and let
be the algebra of all finite unions of rational closed-open intervals contained in
. It is easy to prove that
is, in fact, an algebra. It is also easy to see that the cardinal of every non-empty set in
is
.
Let
be the counting set function (
) defined in
. It is clear that
is finitely additive and
-additive in
. Since every non-empty set in
is infinite, then, for every non-empty set
,
Now, let
be the
-algebra generated by
. It is easy to see that
is the
-algebra of all subsets of
, and both
and
are measures defined on
and both are extensions of
. Note that, in this case, the two extensions are
-finite, because
is countable.
Via Fubini's theorem
Another example is closely related to the failure of some forms of Fubini's theorem for spaces that are not σ-finite.Suppose that
is the unit interval with Lebesgue measure and
is the unit interval with the discrete counting measure. Let the ring
be generated by products
where
is Lebesgue measurable and
is any subset, and give this set the measure
. This has a very large number of different extensions to a measure; for example:
- The measure of a subset is the sum of the measures of its horizontal sections. This is the smallest possible extension. Here the diagonal has measure 0.
- The measure of a subset is
where
is the number of points of the subset with given
-coordinate. The diagonal has measure 1.
- The Carathéodory extension, which is the largest possible extension. Any subset of finite measure is contained in some union of a countable number of horizontal lines. In particular the diagonal has measure infinity.
See also
- Outer measure: the proof of Carathéodory's extension theorem is based upon the outer measure concept.
- Loeb measures, constructed using Carathéodory's extension theorem.
Notes and References
- Quoting Paul Loya: "Warning: I've seen the following theorem called the Carathéodory extension theorem, the Carathéodory-Fréchet extension theorem, the Carathéodory-Hopf extension theorem, the Hopf extension theorem, the Hahn-Kolmogorov extension theorem, and many others that I can't remember! We shall simply call it Extension Theorem. However, I read in Folland's book (p. 41) that the theorem is originally due to Maurice René Fréchet (1878–1973) who proved it in 1924." Paul Loya (page 33).
- Book: Klenke. Achim. Probability Theory. 2014. 978-1-4471-5360-3. Theorem 1.53. 10.1007/978-1-4471-5361-0. Universitext.
- Web site: Noel. Vaillant. Caratheodory's Extension. Probability.net. Theorem 4.
- Book: Ash, Robert B.. Probability and Measure Theory. Academic Press. 2nd. 1999. 0-12-065202-1. 19.