Forcing (computability) explained
Forcing in computability theory is a modification of Paul Cohen's original set-theoretic technique of forcing to deal with computability concerns.
Conceptually the two techniques are quite similar: in both one attempts to build generic objects (intuitively objects that are somehow 'typical') by meeting dense sets. Both techniques are described as a relation (customarily denoted
) between 'conditions' and sentences. However, where set-theoretic forcing is usually interested in creating objects that meet every dense set of conditions in the ground model, computability-theoretic forcing only aims to meet dense sets that are arithmetically or hyperarithmetically definable. Therefore, some of the more difficult machinery used in set-theoretic forcing can be eliminated or substantially simplified when defining forcing in computability. But while the machinery may be somewhat different, computability-theoretic and set-theoretic forcing are properly regarded as an application of the same technique to different classes of formulas.
Terminology
In this article we use the following terminology.
- real: an element of
. In other words, a function that maps each integer to either 0 or 1.
- string: an element of
. In other words, a finite approximation to a real.
- notion of forcing: A notion of forcing is a set
and a partial order on
,
with a
greatest element
.
- condition: An element in a notion of forcing. We say a condition
is stronger than a condition
just when
.
- compatible conditions: Given conditions
say that
and
are compatible if there is a condition
such that with respect to
, both
and
can be simultaneously satisfied if they are true or allowed to coexist.
means
and
are incompatible.
- Filter : A subset
of a notion of forcing
is a filter if
, and
p\inF\landq\succPp\impliesq\inF
. In other words, a filter is a compatible set of conditions closed under weakening of conditions.
- Ultrafilter: A maximal filter, i.e.,
is an ultrafilter if
is a filter and there is no filter
properly containing
.
- Cohen forcing: The notion of forcing
where conditions are elements of
and
(\tau\succC\sigma\iff\sigma\supset\tau
)
Note that for Cohen forcing
is the
reverse of the containment relation. This leads to an unfortunate notational confusion where some computability theorists reverse the direction of the forcing partial order (exchanging
with
, which is more natural for Cohen forcing, but is at odds with the notation used in set theory).
Generic objects
The intuition behind forcing is that our conditions are finite approximations to some object we wish to build and that
is stronger than
when
agrees with everything
says about the object we are building and adds some information of its own. For instance in Cohen forcing the conditions can be viewed as finite approximations to a real and if
then
tells us the value of the real at more places.
In a moment we will define a relation
(read
forces
) that holds between conditions (elements of
) and sentences, but first we need to explain the
language that
is a sentence for. However, forcing is a technique, not a definition, and the language for
will depend on the application one has in mind and the choice of
.
The idea is that our language should express facts about the object we wish to build with our forcing construction.
Forcing relation
The forcing relation
was developed by
Paul Cohen, who introduced forcing as a technique for proving the independence of certain statements from the standard axioms of set theory, particularly the
continuum hypothesis (CH).
The notation
is used to express that a particular condition or generic set forces a certain proposition or formula
to be true in the resulting forcing extension. Here's
represents the original universe of sets (the ground model),
denotes the forcing relation, and
is a statement in set theory.When
, it means that in a suitable forcing extension, the statement
will be true.
References
- Book: Fitting
, Melvin
. Melvin Fitting. 1981. Fundamentals of generalized recursion theory. North-Holland Publishing Company. Amsterdam, New York, and Oxford. Studies in Logic and the Foundations of Mathematics. 1078–1079. 10.2307/2273928. 105. 2273928. 118376273.
- Book: Odifreddi
, Piergiorgio
. Piergiorgio Odifreddi. 1999. Classical recursion theory. Vol. II. North-Holland Publishing Company. Amsterdam. Studies in Logic and the Foundations of Mathematics. 978-0-444-50205-6 . 1718169 . 143.