Extension by new constant and function names explained

In mathematical logic, a theory can be extended withnew constants or function names under certain conditions with assurance that the extension will introduceno contradiction. Extension by definitions is perhaps the best-known approach, but it requiresunique existence of an object with the desired property. Addition of new names can also be donesafely without uniqueness.

Suppose that a closed formula

\existsx1\ldots\existsxm\varphi(x1,\ldots,xm)

T

. Let

T1

be a theory obtained from

T

by extending its language with new constants

a1,\ldots,am

\varphi(a1,\ldots,am)

.

Then

T1

is a conservative extension of

T

, which means that the theory

T1

has the same set of theorems in the original language (i.e., without constants

ai

) as the theory

T

.

Such a theory can also be conservatively extended by introducing a new functional symbol:[1]

Suppose that a closed formula

\forall\vec{x}\existsy\varphi(y,\vec{x})

is a theorem of a first-order theory

T

, where we denote

\vec{x}:=(x1,\ldots,xn)

. Let

T1

be a theory obtained from

T

by extending its language with a new functional symbol

f

(of arity

n

) and adding a new axiom

\forall\vec{x}\varphi(f(\vec{x}),\vec{x})

. Then

T1

is a conservative extension of

T

, i.e. the theories

T

and

T1

prove the same theorems not involving the functional symbol

f

).

Shoenfield states the theorem in the form for a new function name, and constants are the same as functionsof zero arguments. In formal systems that admit ordered tuples, extension by multiple constants as shown here can be accomplished by addition of a new constant tuple and the new constant names having the values of elements of the tuple.

See also

Notes and References

  1. Book: Joseph Shoenfield

    . Shoenfield . Joseph . Joseph Shoenfield. Mathematical Logic . 1967 . 55–56. Addison-Wesley.