Ergodicity economics is a research programme aimed at reworking the theoretical foundations of economics in the context of ergodic theory.[1] The project's main goal is to understand how traditional economic theory, framed in terms of the expectation values of ensembles, changes when replacing expectation value averages with time averages. In particular, the programme is interested in understanding the effect of non-ergodic processes in economics, that is processes where the expectation value of an observable does not equal its time average.
Ergodicity economics questions whether expected value is a useful indicator of performance over time. In doing so it builds on existing critiques of the use of expected value in the modeling of economic decisions. Such critiques started soon after the introduction of expected value in 1654. For instance, expected-utility theory was proposed in 1738 by Daniel Bernoulli[2] as a way of modeling behavior which is inconsistent with expected-value maximization. In 1956, John Kelly devised the Kelly criterion by optimizing the use of available information, and Leo Breiman later noted that this is equivalent to optimizing time-average performance, as opposed to expected value.[3]
The ergodicity economics research programme originates in two papers by Ole Peters in 2011, a theoretical physicist and current external professor at the Santa Fe Institute.[4] The first studied the problem of optimal leverage in finance and how this may be achieved by considering the non-ergodic properties of geometric brownian motion.[5] The second paper applied principles of non-ergodicity to propose a possible solution for the St. Petersburg paradox.[6] More recent work has suggested possible solutions for the equity premium puzzle, the insurance puzzle, gamble-selection, probability weighting, and has provided insights into the dynamics of income inequality.[7]
Ergodic theory is a branch of mathematics which investigates the relationship between time averages and expected values (or, equivalently, ensemble averages) in dynamical systems and stochastic process|stochastic processes]. Ergodicity economics inherits from this branch the probing of this relationship in stochastic processes used as economic models. Early economic theory was developed at a time when the expected value had been invented but its relation to the time average was unclear. No clear distinction was made between the two mathematical objects, which amounts to an implicit assumption of ergodicity.
Ergodicity economics explores what aspects of economics can be informed by avoiding this implicit assumption.
Mean values and expected values are used extensively in economic theory, most commonly as a summary statistic. One common critique of this practice is the sensitivity of mean values to outliers. Ergodicity economics focuses on a different critique and emphasizes the physical meaning of expected values as averages across a statistical ensemble of parallel systems. It insists on a physical justification when expected values are used. In essence, at least one of two conditions must hold:
In ergodicity economics, expected values are replaced, where necessary, by averages that account for the ergodicity or non-ergodicity of the observables involved.
Ergodicity economics emphasizes what happens to an agent's wealth
x(t)
t
g
x(t)
g= | \Deltav(x) |
\Deltat |
v(x)
x(t)
Growth processes
x(t)
gt
v(x)
gt=
E[\Deltav(x)] | |
\Deltat |
In this context,
v(x)
An influential class of models for economic decision-making is known as expected utility theory. The following specific model can be mapped to the growth-rate optimization highlighted by ergodicity economics. Here, agents evaluate monetary wealth
x
u(x)
E[\Deltau(x)]
This model was proposed as an improvement of expected-value maximization, where agents maximize
E[\Deltax]
Comparing (2) to (1), we can identify the utility function
u(x)
v(x)
\Deltat
\Deltat
This mapping shows that the two models will yield identical predictions if the utility function applied under expected-utility theory is the same as the ergodicity transformation, needed to compute an ergodic growth rate.
Ergodicity economics thus emphasizes the dynamic circumstances under which a decision is made, whereas expected-utility theory emphasizes idiosyncratic preferences to explain behavior. Different ergodicity transformations indicate different types of wealth dynamics, whereas different utility functions indicate different personal preferences. The mapping highlights the relationship between the two approaches, showing that differences in personal preferences can arise purely as a result of different dynamic contexts of decision makers.
A simple example for an agent's wealth process,
x(t)
x(t)
dx=x(t)(\mudt+\sigmadWt)
where
dWt
\mu
\sigma
x(t)=x(0)\exp\left(\left(\mu-
\sigma2 | |
2 |
\right)t+\sigmaWt\right)
In this case the ergodicity transformation is
v(x)=ln(x)
lnx(t)=lnx(0)+\left(\mu-
\sigma2 | |
2 |
\right)t+\sigmaWt
Following the recipe laid out above, this leads to the time-average growth rate
gt=
E[\Deltav(x)] | |
\Deltat |
=\mu-
\sigma2 | |
2 |
It follows that for geometric Brownian motion, maximizing the rate of change in the logarithmic utility function,
u(x)=ln(x)
Stochastic processes other than (3) possess different ergodicity transformations, where growth-optimal agents maximize the expected value of utility functions other than the logarithm. Trivially, replacing (3) with additive dynamics implies a linear ergodicity transformation, and many similar pairs of dynamics and transformations can be derived.
A popular illustration of non-ergodicity in economic processes is a repeated multiplicative coin toss, an instance of the binomial multiplicative process.[10] It demonstrates how an expected-value analysis can indicate that a gamble is favorable although the gambler is guaranteed to lose over time.
In this thought experiment, discussed in,[7] a person participates in a simple game where they toss a fair coin. If the coin lands heads, the person gains 50% on their current wealth; if it lands tails, the person loses 40%.
The game shows the difference between the expected value of an investment, or bet, and the time-average or real-world outcome of repeatedly engaging in that bet over time.
Denoting current wealth by
x(t)
t+\deltat
x(t+\deltat)
1.5 x x(t)
0.6 x x(t)
pH=pT=1/2
\begin{align} E[x(t+\deltat)]&=pH x 1.5x(t)+pT x 0.6x(t)\\ &=1.05x(t). \end{align}
By induction, after
T
E[x(t+T\deltat)]=1.05Tx(t)
This calculation shows that the game is favorable in expectation—its expected value increases with each round played.
The time-average performance indicates what happens to the wealth of a single gambler who plays repeatedly, reinvesting their entire wealth every round. Due to compounding, after
T
x(t+T\delta
T | |
t)=\prod | |
\tau=1 |
r\taux(t),
where we have written
r\tau
\tauth
r\tau=rH=1.5
r\tau=rT=0.6
\bar{r} | ||||
|
\right)1/T.
Introducing the notation
nH
\bar{r}T=
nH | |
\left(r | |
H |
T-nH | |
r | |
T |
\right)1/T
nH/T | |
=r | |
H |
(T-nH)/T | |
r | |
T |
.
For any finite
T
\bar{r}T
T\toinfty
\limT\toinfty\bar{r}T=\left(rHrT
| ||||
\right) |
≈ 0.95.
The comparison between expected value and time-average performance illustrates an effect of broken ergodicity: over time, with probability one, wealth decreases by about 5% per round, in contrast to the increase by 5% per round of the expected value.
In December 2020, Bloomberg news published an article titled "Everything We’ve Learned About Modern Economic Theory Is Wrong"[11] discussing the implications of ergodicity in economics following the publication of a review of the subject in Nature Physics. Morningstar covered the story to discuss the investment case for stock diversification.[12]
In the book Skin in the Game, Nassim Nicholas Taleb suggests that the ergodicity problem requires a rethinking of how economists use probabilities.[13] A summary of the arguments was published by Taleb in a Medium article in August 2017.[14]
In the book The End of Theory, Richard Bookstaber lists non-ergodicity as one of four characteristics of our economy that are part of financial crises, that conventional economics fails to adequately account for, and that any model of such crises needs to take adequate account of.[15] The other three are: computational irreducibility, emergent phenomena, and radical uncertainty.
In the book The Ergodic Investor and Entrepreneur, Boyd and Reardon tackle the practical implications of non-ergodic capital growth for investors and entrepreneurs, especially for those with a sustainability, circular economy, net positive, or regenerative focus.[16]
James White and Victor Haghani discuss the field of ergodicity economics in their book The Missing Billionaires.[17]
It has been claimed that expected utility theory implicitly assumes ergodicity in the sense that it optimizes an expected value which is only relevant to the long-term benefit of the decision-maker if the relevant observable is ergodic.[18] Doctor, Wakker, and Tang argue that this is wrong because such assumptions are “outside the scope of expected utility theory as a static theory”.[19] They further argue that ergodicity economics overemphasizes the importance of long-term growth as “the primary factor that explains economic phenomena,” and downplays the importance of individual preferences. They also caution against optimizing long-term growth inappropriately. An example is given of a short-term decision between A) a great loss incurred with certainty and B) a gain enjoyed with almost-certainty paired with an even greater loss at negligible probability. In the example the long-term growth rate favors the certain loss and seems an inappropriate criterion for the short-term decision horizon. Finally, an experiment by Meder and colleagues claims to find that individual risk preferences change with dynamical conditions in ways predicted by ergodicity economics.[20] Doctor, Wakker, and Tang criticize the experiment for being confounded by differences in ambiguity and the complexity of probability calculations. Further, they criticize the analysis for applying static expected utility theory models to a context where dynamic versions are more appropriate. In support of this, Goldstein claims to show that multi-period EUT predicts a similar change in risk preferences as observed in the experiment.[21]