Confidence interval explained
Informally, in frequentist statistics, a confidence interval (CI) is an interval which is expected to typically contain the parameter being estimated. More specifically, given a confidence level
(95% and 99% are typical values), a CI is a
random interval which contains the parameter being estimated
% of the time.
[1] [2] The
confidence level,
degree of confidence or
confidence coefficient represents the long-run
proportion of CIs (at the given confidence level) that theoretically contain the
true value of the parameter; this is tantamount to the
nominal coverage probability. For example, out of all intervals computed at the 95% level, 95% of them should contain the parameter's true value.
[3] Factors affecting the width of the CI include the sample size, the variability in the sample, and the confidence level.[4] All else being the same, a larger sample produces a narrower confidence interval, greater variability in the sample produces a wider confidence interval, and a higher confidence level produces a wider confidence interval.[5]
Definition
Let
be a
random sample from a
probability distribution with
statistical parameter
, which is a quantity to be estimated, and
, representing quantities that are not of immediate interest. A confidence interval for the parameter
, with confidence level or coefficient
, is an interval
determined by
random variables
and
with the property:
P(u(X)<\theta<v(X))=\gamma forevery(\theta,\varphi).
The number
, whose typical value is close to but not greater than 1, is sometimes given in the form
(or as a percentage
), where
is a small positive number, often 0.05.
It is important for the bounds
and
to be specified in such a way that as long as
is collected randomly, every time we compute a confidence interval, there is probability
that it would contain
, the true value of the parameter being estimated. This should hold true for any actual
and
.
[2] Approximate confidence intervals
In many applications, confidence intervals that have exactly the required confidence level are hard to construct, but approximate intervals can be computed. The rule for constructing the interval may be accepted as providing a confidence interval at level
if
P(u(X)<\theta<v(X)) ≈ \gamma forevery(\theta,\varphi)
to an acceptable level of approximation. Alternatively, some authors[6] simply require that
P(u(X)<\theta<v(X))\ge \gamma forevery(\theta,\varphi),
which is useful if the probabilities are only partially identified or imprecise, and also when dealing with discrete distributions. Confidence limits of the form
and
are called conservative;[7] accordingly, one speaks of conservative confidence intervals and, in general, regions.
Desired properties
When applying standard statistical procedures, there will often be standard ways of constructing confidence intervals. These will have been devised so as to meet certain desirable properties, which will hold given that the assumptions on which the procedure relies are true. These desirable properties may be described as: validity, optimality, and invariance.
Of the three, "validity" is most important, followed closely by "optimality". "Invariance" may be considered as a property of the method of derivation of a confidence interval, rather than of the rule for constructing the interval. In non-standard applications, these same desirable properties would be sought:
Validity
This means that the nominal coverage probability (confidence level) of the confidence interval should hold, either exactly or to a good approximation.
Optimality
This means that the rule for constructing the confidence interval should make as much use of the information in the data-set as possible.
One way of assessing optimality is by the width of the interval so that a rule for constructing a confidence interval is judged better than another if it leads to intervals whose widths are typically shorter.
Invariance
In many applications, the quantity being estimated might not be tightly defined as such.
For example, a survey might result in an estimate of the median income in a population, but it might equally be considered as providing an estimate of the logarithm of the median income, given that this is a common scale for presenting graphical results. It would be desirable that the method used for constructing a confidence interval for the median income would give equivalent results when applied to constructing a confidence interval for the logarithm of the median income: Specifically the values at the ends of the latter interval would be the logarithms of the values at the ends of former interval.
Methods of derivation
For non-standard applications, there are several routes that might be taken to derive a rule for the construction of confidence intervals. Established rules for standard procedures might be justified or explained via several of these routes. Typically a rule for constructing confidence intervals is closely tied to a particular way of finding a point estimate of the quantity being considered.
Summary statistics
This is closely related to the method of moments for estimation. A simple example arises where the quantity to be estimated is the population mean, in which case a natural estimate is the sample mean. Similarly, the sample variance can be used to estimate the population variance. A confidence interval for the true mean can be constructed centered on the sample mean with a width which is a multiple of the square root of the sample variance.
Likelihood theory
Estimates can be constructed using the maximum likelihood principle, the likelihood theory for this provides two ways of constructing confidence intervals or confidence regions for the estimates.
Estimating equations
The estimation approach here can be considered as both a generalization of the method of moments and a generalization of the maximum likelihood approach. There are corresponding generalizations of the results of maximum likelihood theory that allow confidence intervals to be constructed based on estimates derived from estimating equations.
Hypothesis testing
If hypothesis tests are available for general values of a parameter, then confidence intervals/regions can be constructed by including in the confidence region all those points for which the hypothesis test of the null hypothesis that the true value is the given value is not rejected at a significance level of [7]
Bootstrapping
In situations where the distributional assumptions for the above methods are uncertain or violated, resampling methods allow construction of confidence intervals or prediction intervals. The observed data distribution and the internal correlations are used as the surrogate for the correlations in the wider population.
Central limit theorem
The central limit theorem is a refinement of the law of large numbers. For a large number of independent identically distributed random variables
with finite variance, the average
approximately has a normal distribution, no matter what the distribution of the
is, with the approximation roughly improving in proportion to
.
[2] Example
Suppose
is an
independent sample from a
normally distributed population with unknown parameters
mean
and
variance
Let
},
}\sum_^n (X_i - \bar)^2.
Where
is the
sample mean, and
is the sample variance. Then
has a Student's t distribution with
degrees of freedom.
[8] Note that the distribution of
does not depend on the values of the unobservable parameters
and
; i.e., it is a
pivotal quantity. Suppose we wanted to calculate a 95% confidence interval for
Then, denoting
as the 97.5th
percentile of this distribution,
Note that "97.5th" and "0.95" are correct in the preceding expressions. There is a 2.5% chance that
will be less than
and a 2.5% chance that it will be larger than
Thus, the probability that
will be between
and
is 95%.
is the probability measure under the student
distribution.
Consequently,
} \leq \mu \leq \bar + \frac\right) = 0.95,
and we have a theoretical (stochastic) 95% confidence interval for
Here
is the probability measure under unknown distribution of
.
After observing the sample we find values
for
and
for
from which we compute the confidence interval
}, \bar + \frac\right].
Interpretation
Various interpretations of a confidence interval can be given (taking the 95% confidence interval as an example in the following).
- The confidence interval can be expressed in terms of a long-run frequency in repeated samples (or in resampling): "Were this procedure to be repeated on numerous samples, the proportion of calculated 95% confidence intervals that encompassed the true value of the population parameter would tend toward 95%."
- The confidence interval can be expressed in terms of probability with respect to a single theoretical (yet to be realized) sample: "There is a 95% probability that the 95% confidence interval calculated from a given future sample will cover the true value of the population parameter." This essentially reframes the "repeated samples" interpretation as a probability rather than a frequency.
See also: Neyman construction.
- The confidence interval can be expressed in terms of statistical significance, e.g.: "The 95% confidence interval represents values that are not statistically significantly different from the point estimate at the .05 level."[9]
Common misunderstandings
Confidence intervals and levels are frequently misunderstood, and published studies have shown that even professional scientists often misinterpret them.[10] [11] [12] [13] [14] [15]
- A 95% confidence level does not mean that for a given realized interval there is a 95% probability that the population parameter lies within the interval (i.e., a 95% probability that the interval covers the population parameter). According to the frequentist interpretation, once an interval is calculated, this interval either covers the parameter value or it does not; it is no longer a matter of probability. The 95% probability relates to the reliability of the estimation procedure, not to a specific calculated interval.[16] Neyman himself (the original proponent of confidence intervals) made this point in his original paper:
It will be noticed that in the above description, the probability statements refer to the problems of estimation with which the statistician will be concerned in the future. In fact, I have repeatedly stated that the frequency of correct results will tend to α. Consider now the case when a sample is already drawn, and the calculations have given [particular limits]. Can we say that in this particular case the probability of the true value [falling between these limits] is equal to α? The answer is obviously in the negative. The parameter is an unknown constant, and no probability statement concerning its value may be made...
- A 95% confidence level does not mean that 95% of the sample data lie within the confidence interval.
- A 95% confidence level does not mean that there is a 95% probability of the parameter estimate from a repeat of the experiment falling within the confidence interval computed from a given experiment.
Examples of how naïve interpretation of confidence intervals can be problematic
Confidence procedure for uniform location
Welch[17] presented an example which clearly shows the difference between the theory of confidence intervals and other theories of interval estimation (including Fisher's fiducial intervals and objective Bayesian intervals). Robinson[18] called this example "[p]ossibly the best known counterexample for Neyman's version of confidence interval theory." To Welch, it showed the superiority of confidence interval theory; to critics of the theory, it shows a deficiency. Here we present a simplified version.
Suppose that
are independent observations from a
uniform
distribution. Then the optimal 50% confidence procedure for
is
[19] \bar{X}\pm\begin{cases}
\dfrac{|X1-X2|}{2}&if|X1-X2|<1/2\\[8pt]
\dfrac{1-|X1-X2|}{2}&if|X1-X2|\geq1/2.
\end{cases}
A fiducial or objective Bayesian argument can be used to derive the interval estimate
which is also a 50% confidence procedure. Welch showed that the first confidence procedure dominates the second, according to desiderata from confidence interval theory; for every
, the probability that the first procedure contains
is
less than or equal to the probability that the second procedure contains
. The average width of the intervals from the first procedure is less than that of the second. Hence, the first procedure is preferred under classical confidence interval theory.
However, when
, intervals from the first procedure are
guaranteed to contain the true value
: Therefore, the nominal 50% confidence coefficient is unrelated to the uncertainty we should have that a specific interval contains the true value. The second procedure does not have this property.
Moreover, when the first procedure generates a very short interval, this indicates that
are very close together and hence only offer the information in a single data point. Yet the first interval will exclude almost all reasonable values of the parameter due to its short width. The second procedure does not have this property.
The two counter-intuitive properties of the first procedure – 100% coverage when
are far apart and almost 0% coverage when
are close together – balance out to yield 50% coverage on average. However, despite the first procedure being optimal, its intervals offer neither an assessment of the precision of the estimate nor an assessment of the uncertainty one should have that the interval contains the true value.
This example is used to argue against naïve interpretations of confidence intervals. If a confidence procedure is asserted to have properties beyond that of the nominal coverage (such as relation to precision, or a relationship with Bayesian inference), those properties must be proved; they do not follow from the fact that a procedure is a confidence procedure.
Confidence procedure for ω2
Steiger[20] suggested a number of confidence procedures for common effect size measures in ANOVA. Morey et al. point out that several of these confidence procedures, including the one for ω2, have the property that as the F statistic becomes increasingly small—indicating misfit with all possible values of ω2—the confidence interval shrinks and can even contain only the single value ω2 = 0; that is, the CI is infinitesimally narrow (this occurs when
for a
CI).
This behavior is consistent with the relationship between the confidence procedure and significance testing: as F becomes so small that the group means are much closer together than we would expect by chance, a significance test might indicate rejection for most or all values of ω2. Hence the interval will be very narrow or even empty (or, by a convention suggested by Steiger, containing only 0). However, this does not indicate that the estimate of ω2 is very precise. In a sense, it indicates the opposite: that the trustworthiness of the results themselves may be in doubt. This is contrary to the common interpretation of confidence intervals that they reveal the precision of the estimate.
History
Methods for calculating confidence intervals for the binomial proportion appeared from the 1920s.[21] [22] The main ideas of confidence intervals in general were developed in the early 1930s,[23] [24] [25] and the first thorough and general account was given by Jerzy Neyman in 1937.
Neyman described the development of the ideas as follows (reference numbers have been changed):
[My work on confidence intervals] originated about 1930 from a simple question of Waclaw Pytkowski, then my student in Warsaw, engaged in an empirical study in farm economics. The question was: how to characterize non-dogmatically the precision of an estimated regression coefficient? ...
Pytkowski's monograph ... appeared in print in 1932.[26] It so happened that, somewhat earlier, Fisher published his first paper[27] concerned with fiducial distributions and fiducial argument. Quite unexpectedly, while the conceptual framework of fiducial argument is entirely different from that of confidence intervals, the specific solutions of several particular problems coincided. Thus, in the first paper in which I presented the theory of confidence intervals, published in 1934, I recognized Fisher's priority for the idea that interval estimation is possible without any reference to Bayes' theorem and with the solution being independent from probabilities a priori. At the same time I mildly suggested that Fisher's approach to the problem involved a minor misunderstanding.
In medical journals, confidence intervals were promoted in the 1970s but only became widely used in the 1980s.[28] By 1988, medical journals were requiring the reporting of confidence intervals.[29]
See also
Confidence interval for specific distributions
- Confidence interval for binomial distribution
- Confidence interval for exponent of the power law distribution
- Confidence interval for mean of the exponential distribution
- Confidence interval for mean of the Poisson distribution
- Confidence intervals for mean and variance of the normal distribution
- Confidence interval for predicted response in simple linear regression
Bibliography
- Fisher, R.A. (1956) Statistical Methods and Scientific Inference. Oliver and Boyd, Edinburgh. (See p. 32.)
- Freund, J.E. (1962) Mathematical Statistics Prentice Hall, Englewood Cliffs, NJ. (See pp. 227–228.)
- Hacking, I. (1965) Logic of Statistical Inference. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge.
- Keeping, E.S. (1962) Introduction to Statistical Inference. D. Van Nostrand, Princeton, NJ.
- Kiefer . J. . Jack Kiefer (mathematician) . 1977 . Conditional Confidence Statements and Confidence Estimators (with discussion) . 2286460 . Journal of the American Statistical Association . 72 . 360a. 789–827 . 10.1080/01621459.1977.10479956.
- Mayo, D. G. (1981) "In defence of the Neyman–Pearson theory of confidence intervals", Philosophy of Science, 48 (2), 269–280. .
- Mehta, S. (2014) Statistics Topics. .
- Morey. R. D.. Hoekstra. R.. Rouder. J. N.. Lee. M. D.. Wagenmakers. E.-J.. The fallacy of placing confidence in confidence intervals. Psychonomic Bulletin & Review. 23. 1. 2016. 103–123. 10.3758/s13423-015-0947-8. 26450628. 4742505.
- Neyman, J. (1937) "Outline of a Theory of Statistical Estimation Based on the Classical Theory of Probability" Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society of London A, 236, 333–380. (Seminal work)
- Robinson . G.K. . 1975 . Some Counterexamples to the Theory of Confidence Intervals . 2334498 . Biometrika . 62 . 1. 155–161 . 10.1093/biomet/62.1.155.
- Savage, L. J. (1962), The Foundations of Statistical Inference. Methuen, London.
- Smithson, M. (2003) Confidence intervals. Quantitative Applications in the Social Sciences Series, No. 140. Belmont, CA: SAGE Publications. .
External links
Notes and References
- Book: Zar, Jerrold H.. Biostatistical Analysis. Prentice Hall. 199. 978-0130815422. 4th. Upper Saddle River, N.J.. 43–45. 39498633.
- Dekking. Frederik Michel. Kraaikamp. Cornelis. Lopuhaä. Hendrik Paul. Meester. Ludolf Erwin. 2005. A Modern Introduction to Probability and Statistics. Springer Texts in Statistics. en-gb. 10.1007/1-84628-168-7. 978-1-85233-896-1. 1431-875X.
- Book: Introductory statistics. Illowsky, Barbara. Dean, Susan L., 1945-, Illowsky, Barbara., OpenStax College. 978-1-947172-05-0. Houston, Texas. 899241574.
- Hazra. Avijit. October 2017. Using the confidence interval confidently. Journal of Thoracic Disease. 9. 10. 4125–4130. 10.21037/jtd.2017.09.14. 2072-1439. 5723800. 29268424 . free .
- Book: Khare. Vikas. Ocean Energy Modeling and Simulation with Big Data Computational Intelligence for System Optimization and Grid Integration. Nema. Savita. Baredar. Prashant. 2020. Butterworth-Heinemann . 978-0-12-818905-4. English. 1153294021.
- Book: Roussas, George G. . 1997 . A Course in Mathematical Statistics . 2nd . Academic Press . 397.
- Book: Cox, D.R. . Hinkley, D.V. . 1974 . Theoretical Statistics . Chapman & Hall.
- Rees, D.G. (2001). Essential Statistics, 4th Edition, Chapman and Hall/CRC. (Section 9.5)
- Cox D.R., Hinkley D.V. (1974) Theoretical Statistics, Chapman & Hall, pp. 214, 225, 233
- Web site: Kalinowski. Pawel. Identifying Misconceptions about Confidence Intervals. 2010. 2021-12-22.
- Web site: Archived copy . 2014-09-16 . https://web.archive.org/web/20160304043241/http://irt.com.ne.kr/data/researchers%20misunderstand%20ci%20and%20error%20bars.pdf . 2016-03-04 . dead .
- Hoekstra, R., R. D. Morey, J. N. Rouder, and E-J. Wagenmakers, 2014. Robust misinterpretation of confidence intervals. Psychonomic Bulletin & Review Vol. 21, No. 5, pp. 1157-1164. http://www.ejwagenmakers.com/inpress/HoekstraEtAlPBR.pdf
- https://www.sciencenews.org/blog/context/scientists-grasp-confidence-intervals-doesnt-inspire-confidence Scientists' grasp of confidence intervals doesn't inspire confidence
- Greenland. Sander. Senn. Stephen J.. Rothman. Kenneth J.. Carlin. John B.. Poole. Charles. Goodman. Steven N.. Altman. Douglas G.. April 2016 . Statistical tests, P values, confidence intervals, and power: a guide to misinterpretations. European Journal of Epidemiology . 31. 4. 337–350. 10.1007/s10654-016-0149-3. 0393-2990. 4877414. 27209009.
- Helske . Jouni . Helske . Satu . Cooper . Matthew . Ynnerman . Anders . Besancon . Lonni . Can Visualization Alleviate Dichotomous Thinking? Effects of Visual Representations on the Cliff Effect . IEEE Transactions on Visualization and Computer Graphics . Institute of Electrical and Electronics Engineers (IEEE) . 27 . 8 . 2021-08-01 . 1077-2626 . 10.1109/tvcg.2021.3073466. 2002.07671 . 3397–3409. 33856998 . 233230810 .
- Web site: 1.3.5.2. Confidence Limits for the Mean. nist.gov. 2014-09-16. https://web.archive.org/web/20080205120031/http://www.itl.nist.gov/div898/handbook/eda/section3/eda352.htm. 2008-02-05. dead.
- Welch. B. L. . 1939. On Confidence Limits and Sufficiency, with Particular Reference to Parameters of Location. 2235987 . The Annals of Mathematical Statistics. 10. 1. 58–69. 10.1214/aoms/1177732246. free.
- Robinson. G. K. . 1975. Some Counterexamples to the Theory of Confidence Intervals. 2334498 . Biometrika. 62. 1. 155–161. 10.2307/2334498.
- Pratt. J. W. . 1961. Book Review: Testing Statistical Hypotheses. by E. L. Lehmann. 2282344 . Journal of the American Statistical Association. 56. 293. 163–167. 10.1080/01621459.1961.10482103.
- Steiger. J. H. . 2004. Beyond the F test: Effect size confidence intervals and tests of close fit in the analysis of variance and contrast analysis. Psychological Methods. 9. 2. 164–182. 10.1037/1082-989x.9.2.164. 15137887 .
- Edwin B. Wilson (1927) Probable Inference, the Law of Succession, and Statistical Inference, Journal of the American Statistical Association, 22:158, 209-212, https://doi.org/10.1080/01621459.1927.10502953
- C.J. Clopper, E.S. Pearson, The use of confidence or fiducial limits illustrated in the case of the binomial, Biometrika 26(4), 1934, pages 404–413, https://doi.org/10.1093/biomet/26.4.404
- Neyman, J. (1934). On the Two Different Aspects of the Representative Method: The Method of Stratified Sampling and the Method of Purposive Selection. Journal of the Royal Statistical Society, 97(4), 558–625. https://doi.org/10.2307/2342192 (see Note I in the appendix)
- J. Neyman (1935), Ann. Math. Statist. 6(3): 111-116 (September, 1935). https://doi.org/10.1214/aoms/1177732585
- Neyman, J. (1970). A glance at some of my personal experiences in the process of research. In Scientists at Work: Festschrift in honour of Herman Wold. Edited by T. Dalenius, G. Karlsson, S. Malmquist. Almqvist & Wiksell, Stockholm. https://worldcat.org/en/title/195948
- Pytkowski, W., The dependence of the income in small farms upon their area, the outlay and the capital invested in cows. (Polish, English summary) Bibliotaka Palawska, 1932.
- Fisher, R. (1930). Inverse Probability. Mathematical Proceedings of the Cambridge Philosophical Society, 26(4), 528-535. https://doi.org/10.1017/S0305004100016297
- Altman. Douglas G.. 1991. Statistics in medical journals: Developments in the 1980s. Statistics in Medicine. en. 10. 12. 1897–1913. 10.1002/sim.4780101206. 1805317 . 1097-0258.
- Gardner. Martin J.. Altman. Douglas G.. 1988. Estimating with confidence. British Medical Journal. en. 296. 6631. 1210–1211. 10.1136/bmj.296.6631.1210 . 3133015 . 2545695 .