In combinatorial mathematics, the theory of combinatorial species is an abstract, systematic method for deriving the generating functions of discrete structures, which allows one to not merely count these structures but give bijective proofs involving them. Examples of combinatorial species are (finite) graphs, permutations, trees, and so on; each of these has an associated generating function which counts how many structures there are of a certain size. One goal of species theory is to be able to analyse complicated structures by describing them in terms of transformations and combinations of simpler structures. These operations correspond to equivalent manipulations of generating functions, so producing such functions for complicated structures is much easier than with other methods. The theory was introduced, carefully elaborated and applied by Canadian researchers around André Joyal.
The power of the theory comes from its level of abstraction. The "description format" of a structure (such as adjacency list versus adjacency matrix for graphs) is irrelevant, because species are purely algebraic. Category theory provides a useful language for the concepts that arise here, but it is not necessary to understand categories before being able to work with species.
The category of species is equivalent to the category of symmetric sequences in finite sets.
Any species consists of individual combinatorial structures built on the elements of some finite set: for example, a combinatorial graph is a structure of edges among a given set of vertices, and the species of graphs includes all graphs on all finite sets. Furthermore, a member of a species can have its underying set relabeled by the elements of any other equinumerous set, for example relabeling the vertices of a graph gives "the same graph structure" on the new vertices, i.e. an isomorphic graph.
This leads to the formal definition of a combinatorial species. Let
l{B}
F\colonl{B}\tol{B}.
For each finite set A in
l{B}
For example, the "species of permutations" maps each finite set A to the set S[''A''] of all permutations of A (all ways of ordering A into a list), and each bijection f from A to another set B naturally induces a bijection (a relabeling) taking each permutation of A to a corresponding permutation of B, namely a bijection
S[f]:S[A]\toS[B]
Two finite sets are in bijection whenever they have the same cardinality (number of elements); thus by definition the corresponding species sets are also in bijection, and the (finite) cardinality of
F[A]
F(x)=\sumn\operatorname{Card}F[n]
xn | |
n! |
\operatorname{Card}F[n]
F[A]
A=\{1,2,...,n\}
Some examples: writing
fn=\operatorname{Card}F[n]
fn=1
E(x)=ex
fn=n!
S(x)=1/(1-x)
fn=n2
T2(x)=x(x+1)ex
Arithmetic on generating functions corresponds to certain "natural" operations on species. The basic operations are addition, multiplication, composition, and differentiation; it is also necessary to define equality on species. Category theory already has a way of describing when two functors are equivalent: a natural isomorphism. In this context, it just means that for each A there is a bijection between F-structures on A and G-structures on A, which is "well-behaved" in its interaction with transport. Species with the same generating function might not be isomorphic, but isomorphic species do always have the same generating function.
Addition of species is defined by the disjoint union of sets, and corresponds to a choice between structures. For species F and G, define (F + G)[''A''] to be the disjoint union (also written "+") of F[''A''] and G[''A'']. It follows that (F + G)(x) = F(x) + G(x). As a demonstration, take E+ to be the species of non-empty sets, whose generating function is E+(x) = ex − 1, and 1 the species of the empty set, whose generating function is 1(x) = 1. It follows that the sum of the two species E = 1 + E+: in words, "a set is either empty or non-empty". Equations like this can be read as referring to a single structure, as well as to the entire collection of structures.
Multiplying species is slightly more complicated. It is possible to just take the Cartesian product of sets as the definition, but the combinatorial interpretation of this is not quite right. (See below for the use of this kind of product.) Rather than putting together two unrelated structures on the same set, the multiplication operator uses the idea of splitting the set into two components, constructing an F-structure on one and a G-structure on the other.
(F ⋅ G)[A]=\sumA=B+CF[B] x G[C].
The diagram below shows one possible (F · G)-structure on a set with five elements. The F-structure (red) picks up three elements of the base set, and the G-structure (light blue) takes the rest. Other structures will have F and G splitting the set in a different way. The set (F · G)[''A''], where A is the base set, is the disjoint union of all such structures.
The addition and multiplication of species are the most comprehensive expression of the sum and product rules of counting.
Composition, also called substitution, is more complicated again. The basic idea is to replace components of F with G-structures, forming (F ∘ G). As with multiplication, this is done by splitting the input set A; the disjoint subsets are given to G to make G-structures, and the set of subsets is given to F, to make the F-structure linking the G-structures. It is required for G to map the empty set to itself, in order for composition to work. The formal definition is:
(F\circG)[A]=\sum\pi(F[\pi] x \prodBG[B]).
Here, P is the species of partitions, so P[''A''] is the set of all partitions of A. This definition says that an element of (F ∘ G)[''A''] is made up of an F-structure on some partition of A, and a G-structure on each component of the partition. The generating series is
(F\circG)(x)=F(G(x))
One such structure is shown below. Three G-structures (light blue) divide up the five-element base set between them; then, an F-structure (red) is built to connect the G-structures.
These last two operations may be illustrated by the example of trees. First, define X to be the species "singleton" whose generating series is X(x) = x. Then the species Ar of rooted trees (from the French "arborescence") is defined recursively by Ar = X · E(Ar). This equation says that a tree consists of a single root and a set of (sub-)trees. The recursion does not need an explicit base case: it only generates trees in the context of being applied to some finite set. One way to think about this is that the Ar functor is being applied repeatedly to a "supply" of elements from the set - each time, one element is taken by X, and the others distributed by E among the Ar subtrees, until there are no more elements to give to E. This shows that algebraic descriptions of species are quite different from type specifications in programming languages like Haskell.
Likewise, the species P can be characterised as P = E(E+): "a partition is a pairwise disjoint set of nonempty sets (using up all the elements of the input set)". The exponential generating series for P is
P(x)=
(ex-1) | |
e |
Differentiation of species intuitively corresponds to building "structures with a hole", as shown in the illustration below.
Formally,
(F')[A]=F[A\uplus\{\star\}],
where
\star
A
To differentiate the associated exponential series, the sequence of coefficients needs to be shifted one place to the "left" (losing the first term). This suggests a definition for species: F' [''A''] = F[''A'' + {*}], where is a singleton set and "+" is disjoint union. The more advanced parts of the theory of species use differentiation extensively, to construct and solve differential equations on species and series. The idea of adding (or removing) a single part of a structure is a powerful one: it can be used to establish relationships between seemingly unconnected species.
For example, consider a structure of the species L of linear orders - lists of elements of the ground set. Removing an element of a list splits it into two parts (possibly empty); in symbols, this is L = L·L. The exponential generating function of L is L(x) = 1/(1 − x), and indeed:
d | |
dx |
{(1-x)}-1={(1-x)}-2.
The generalized differentiation formulas are to be found in a previous research by N. G. de Bruijn, published in 1964.
The species C of cyclic permutations takes a set A to the set of all cycles on A. Removing a single element from a cycle reduces it to a list: C = L. We can integrate the generating function of L to produce that for C.
C(x)=1+
x | |
\int | |
0 |
dt | |
1-t |
=1+log
1 | |
1-x |
.
A nice example of integration of a species is the completion of a line (coordinatizated by a field) with the infinite point and obtaining a projective line.
There are a variety of other manipulations which may be performed on species. These are necessary to express more complicated structures, such as directed graphs or bigraphs.
Pointing selects a single element in a structure.[4] Given a species F, the corresponding pointed species F• is defined by F•[''A''] = A × F[''A'']. Thus each F•-structure is an F-structure with one element distinguished. Pointing is related to differentiation by the relation F• = X·F' , so F•(x) = x F' (x). The species of pointed sets, E•, is particularly important as a building block for many of the more complex constructions.
The Cartesian product of two species is a species which can build two structures on the same set at the same time. It is different from the ordinary multiplication operator in that all elements of the base set are shared between the two structures. An (F × G)-structure can be seen as a superposition of an F-structure and a G-structure. Bigraphs could be described as the superposition of a graph and a set of trees: each node of the bigraph is part of a graph, and at the same time part of some tree that describes how nodes are nested. The generating function (F × G)(x) is the Hadamard or coefficient-wise product of F(x) and G(x).
The species E• × E• can be seen as making two independent selections from the base set. The two points might coincide, unlike in X·X·E, where they are forced to be different.
As functors, species F and G may be combined by functorial composition:
(F\BoxG)[A]=F[G[A]]
Operations with species are supported by SageMath[5] and, using a special package, also by Haskell.[6] [7]
l{B}k → l{B}
l{B}R
If “finite sets with bijections” is replaced with “finite vector spaces with linear transformations”, then one gets the notion of polynomial functor (after imposing some finiteness condition).
F[A]
F(A)
u:A\toB
F[u]:F[A]\toF[B]
F[A],F[B]