Cardinality of the continuum explained
, sometimes called the
continuum. It is an
infinite cardinal number and is denoted by
(lowercase
Fraktur "
c") or
[1] The real numbers
are more numerous than the
natural numbers
. Moreover,
has the same number of elements as the
power set of
. Symbolically, if the cardinality of
is denoted as
, the cardinality of the continuum isThis was proven by
Georg Cantor in his
uncountability proof of 1874, part of his groundbreaking study of different infinities. The inequality was later stated more simply in his
diagonal argument in 1891. Cantor defined cardinality in terms of
bijective functions: two sets have the same cardinality if, and only if, there exists a bijective function between them.
Between any two real numbers a < b, no matter how close they are to each other, there are always infinitely many other real numbers, and Cantor showed that they are as many as those contained in the whole set of real numbers. In other words, the open interval (a,b) is equinumerous with
, as well as with several other infinite sets, such as any
n-dimensional
Euclidean space
(see
space filling curve). That is,
The smallest infinite cardinal number is
(aleph-null). The second smallest is
(aleph-one). The
continuum hypothesis, which asserts that there are no sets whose cardinality is strictly between
and, means that
.
[2] The truth or falsity of this hypothesis is undecidable and cannot be proven within the widely used
Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory with axiom of choice (ZFC).
Properties
Uncountability
Georg Cantor introduced the concept of cardinality to compare the sizes of infinite sets. He famously showed that the set of real numbers is uncountably infinite. That is,
is strictly greater than the cardinality of the
natural numbers,
:In practice, this means that there are strictly more real numbers than there are integers. Cantor proved this statement in several different ways. For more information on this topic, see
Cantor's first uncountability proof and
Cantor's diagonal argument.
Cardinal equalities
A variation of Cantor's diagonal argument can be used to prove Cantor's theorem, which states that the cardinality of any set is strictly less than that of its power set. That is,
(and so that the power set
of the
natural numbers
is uncountable). In fact, the cardinality of
, by definition
, is equal to
. This can be shown by providing one-to-one mappings in both directions between subsets of a countably infinite set and real numbers, and applying the
Cantor–Bernstein–Schroeder theorem according to which two sets with one-to-one mappings in both directions have the same cardinality.
[3] [4] In one direction, reals can be equated with
Dedekind cuts, sets of rational numbers,
[3] or with their
binary expansions.
[4] In the other direction, the binary expansions of numbers in the half-open interval
, viewed as sets of positions where the expansion is one, almost give a one-to-one mapping from subsets of a countable set (the set of positions in the expansions) to real numbers, but it fails to be one-to-one for numbers with terminating binary expansions, which can also be represented by a non-terminating expansion that ends in a repeating sequence of 1s. This can be made into a one-to-one mapping by that adds one to the non-terminating repeating-1 expansions, mapping them into
.
[4] Thus, we conclude that
[3] [4] The cardinal equality
can be demonstrated using cardinal arithmetic:
By using the rules of cardinal arithmetic, one can also show that
where n is any finite cardinal ≥ 2 and
where
is the cardinality of the power set of
R, and
.
Alternative explanation for
Every real number has at least one infinite decimal expansion. For example,(This is true even in the case the expansion repeats, as in the first two examples.)
In any given case, the number of decimal places is countable since they can be put into a one-to-one correspondence with the set of natural numbers
. This makes it sensible to talk about, say, the first, the one-hundredth, or the millionth decimal place of π. Since the natural numbers have cardinality
each real number has
digits in its expansion.
Since each real number can be broken into an integer part and a decimal fraction, we get:
where we used the fact that
On the other hand, if we map
to
and consider that decimal fractions containing only 3 or 7 are only a part of the real numbers, then we get
and thus
Beth numbers
See main article: Beth number. The sequence of beth numbers is defined by setting
and
. So
is the second beth number,
beth-one:The third beth number,
beth-two, is the cardinality of the power set of
(i.e. the set of all subsets of the
real line):
The continuum hypothesis
See main article: Continuum hypothesis.
The continuum hypothesis asserts that
is also the second
aleph number,
. In other words, the continuum hypothesis states that there is no set
whose cardinality lies strictly between
and
This statement is now known to be independent of the axioms of
Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory with the axiom of choice (ZFC), as shown by
Kurt Gödel and
Paul Cohen.
[5] [6] [7] That is, both the hypothesis and its negation are consistent with these axioms. In fact, for every nonzero
natural number n, the equality
=
is independent of ZFC (case
being the continuum hypothesis). The same is true for most other alephs, although in some cases, equality can be ruled out by
König's theorem on the grounds of
cofinality (e.g.
). In particular,
could be either
or
, where
is the
first uncountable ordinal, so it could be either a
successor cardinal or a
limit cardinal, and either a
regular cardinal or a
singular cardinal.
Sets with cardinality of the continuum
A great many sets studied in mathematics have cardinality equal to
. Some common examples are the following:
Sets with greater cardinality
Sets with cardinality greater than
include:
- the set of all subsets of
(i.e., power set
)
is
isomorphic to
– the indicator function chooses elements of each subset to include)
of all functions from
to
, i.e., the set of all
Lebesgue measurable sets in
.
to
to
,
, and
- the set of all automorphisms of the (discrete) field of complex numbers.
These all have cardinality
(beth two)
See also
References
- Web site: Transfinite number mathematics . 2020-08-12 . Encyclopedia Britannica . en.
- Web site: Weisstein. Eric W.. Continuum. 2020-08-12 . mathworld.wolfram.com . en.
- Stillwell . John . 10.1080/00029890.2002.11919865 . 3 . American Mathematical Monthly . 2695360 . 1903582 . 286–297 . The continuum problem . 109 . 2002.
- Book: Johnson, D. L.
. Elements of Logic via Numbers and Sets . 10.1007/978-1-4471-0603-6_6 . 9781447106036 . Springer Undergraduate Mathematics Series . 113-130 . Springer London . Chapter 6: Cardinal numbers . 1998.
- Book: Gödel, Kurt . 1940-12-31 . Consistency of the Continuum Hypothesis. (AM-3) . 10.1515/9781400881635. 9781400881635 .
- Cohen . Paul J. . The Independence of the Continuum Hypothesis . December 1963 . Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences . 50 . 6 . 1143–1148 . 10.1073/pnas.50.6.1143 . 16578557 . 221287 . 1963PNAS...50.1143C . 0027-8424. free .
- Cohen . Paul J. . The Independence of the Continuum Hypothesis, Ii . January 1964 . Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences . 51 . 1 . 105–110 . 10.1073/pnas.51.1.105 . 16591132 . 300611 . 1964PNAS...51..105C . 0027-8424. free .
Bibliography
- Paul Halmos, Naive set theory. Princeton, NJ: D. Van Nostrand Company, 1960. Reprinted by Springer-Verlag, New York, 1974. (Springer-Verlag edition).
- Jech, Thomas, 2003. Set Theory: The Third Millennium Edition, Revised and Expanded. Springer. .
- Kunen, Kenneth, 1980. . Elsevier. .