Schröder–Bernstein theorem explained
In set theory, the Schröder–Bernstein theorem states that, if there exist injective functions and between the sets and, then there exists a bijective function .
In terms of the cardinality of the two sets, this classically implies that if and, then ; that is, and are equipotent. This is a useful feature in the ordering of cardinal numbers.
The theorem is named after Felix Bernstein and Ernst Schröder. It is also known as the Cantor–Bernstein theorem or Cantor–Schröder–Bernstein theorem, after Georg Cantor, who first published it (albeit without proof).
Proof
The following proof is attributed to Julius König.[1]
Assume without loss of generality that A and B are disjoint. For any a in A or b in B we can form a unique two-sided sequence of elements that are alternately in A and B, by repeatedly applying
and
to go from
A to
B and
and
to go from
B to
A (where defined; the inverses
and
are understood as
partial functions.)
… → f-1(g-1(a)) → g-1(a) → a → f(a) → g(f(a)) → …
For any particular a, this sequence may terminate to the left or not, at a point where
or
is not defined.
By the fact that
and
are injective functions, each
a in
A and
b in
B is in exactly one such sequence to within identity: if an element occurs in two sequences, all elements to the left and to the right must be the same in both, by the definition of the sequences. Therefore, the sequences form a
partition of the (disjoint) union of
A and
B. Hence it suffices to produce a bijection between the elements of
A and
B in each of the sequences separately, as follows:
Call a sequence an A-stopper if it stops at an element of A, or a B-stopper if it stops at an element of B. Otherwise, call it doubly infinite if all the elements are distinct or cyclic if it repeats. See the picture for examples.
- For an A-stopper, the function
is a bijection between its elements in A
and its elements in B
.- For a B-stopper, the function
is a bijection between its elements in B
and its elements in A
.- For a doubly infinite sequence or a cyclic sequence, either
or
will do (
is used in the picture).Examples
- Bijective function from
:
Note:
is the half open set from 0 to 1, including the boundary 0 and excluding the boundary 1.
Let
with
and
with
the two injective functions.
In line with that procedure
C0=\{1\},
\}, C=
Ck=\{1,\tfrac{1}{2},\tfrac{1}{4},\tfrac{1}{8},...\}
Then
h(x)=\begin{cases}
,&for x\inC\\x,&for x\in[0,1]\smallsetminusC\end{cases}
is a bijective function from
.
- Bijective function from
:
Let
with
Then for
one can use the expansions
and
with
and now one can set
g(x;y)=
(10 ⋅ ak+bk) ⋅ 10-2k
which defines an injective function
. (Example:
g(\tfrac{1}{3};\tfrac{2}{3})=0.363636...=\tfrac{12}{33}
)
And therefore a bijective function
can be constructed with the use of
and
.
In this case
is still easy but already
C1=g(f(C0))=g(\{(x;0)|x\in[\tfrac{1}{2},1)\})
gets quite complicated.
Note: Of course there's a more simple way by using the (already bijective) function definition
g2(x;y)=2 ⋅
(10 ⋅ ak+bk) ⋅ 10-2k
. Then
would be the empty set and
for all x.
History
The traditional name "Schröder–Bernstein" is based on two proofs published independently in 1898.Cantor is often added because he first stated the theorem in 1887, while Schröder's name is often omitted because his proof turned out to be flawed while the name of Richard Dedekind, who first proved it, is not connected with the theorem.According to Bernstein, Cantor had suggested the name equivalence theorem (Äquivalenzsatz).[2]
- 1887 Cantor publishes the theorem, however without proof.[3] [2]
- 1887 On July 11, Dedekind proves the theorem (not relying on the axiom of choice) but neither publishes his proof nor tells Cantor about it. Ernst Zermelo discovered Dedekind's proof and in 1908 he publishes his own proof based on the chain theory from Dedekind's paper Was sind und was sollen die Zahlen?[2]
- 1895 Cantor states the theorem in his first paper on set theory and transfinite numbers. He obtains it as an easy consequence of the linear order of cardinal numbers.[4] [5] However, he could not prove the latter theorem, which is shown in 1915 to be equivalent to the axiom of choice by Friedrich Moritz Hartogs.[2]
- 1896 Schröder announces a proof (as a corollary of a theorem by Jevons).[6]
- 1897 Bernstein, a 19-year-old student in Cantor's Seminar, presents his proof.
- 1897 Almost simultaneously, but independently, Schröder finds a proof.
- 1897 After a visit by Bernstein, Dedekind independently proves the theorem a second time.
- 1898 Bernstein's proof (not relying on the axiom of choice) is published by Émile Borel in his book on functions. (Communicated by Cantor at the 1897 International Congress of Mathematicians in Zürich.) In the same year, the proof also appears in Bernstein's dissertation.[7] [2]
- 1898 Schröder publishes his proof which, however, is shown to be faulty by Alwin Reinhold Korselt in 1902 (just before Schröder's death), (confirmed by Schröder),[2] [8] but Korselt's paper is published only in 1911.
Both proofs of Dedekind are based on his famous 1888 memoir Was sind und was sollen die Zahlen? and derive it as a corollary of a proposition equivalent to statement C in Cantor's paper, which reads and implies . Cantor observed this property as early as 1882/83 during his studies in set theory and transfinite numbers and was therefore (implicitly) relying on the axiom of choice.
Prerequisites
The 1895 proof by Cantor relied, in effect, on the axiom of choice by inferring the result as a corollary of the well-ordering theorem.[4] [5] However, König's proof given above shows that the result can also be proved without using the axiom of choice.
On the other hand, König's proof uses the principle of excluded middle to draw a conclusion through case analysis. As such, the above proof is not a constructive one. In fact, in a constructive set theory such as intuitionistic set theory
}, which adopts the full axiom of separation but dispenses with the principle of excluded middle, assuming the Schröder–Bernstein theorem implies the latter.
[9] In turn, there is no proof of König's conclusion in this or weaker constructive theories. Therefore, intuitionists do not accept the statement of the Schröder–Bernstein theorem.
[10] There is also a proof which uses Tarski's fixed point theorem.[11]
See also
References
External links
Notes and References
- J. König. Sur la théorie des ensembles. Comptes Rendus Hebdomadaires des Séances de l'Académie des Sciences. 143. 110–112. 1906.
- – Original edition (1914)
- Reprinted in: Here: p.413 bottom
- Georg Cantor . Beiträge zur Begründung der transfiniten Mengenlehre (1) . . 46 . 4 . 481–512 (Theorem see "Satz B", p.484) . 1895 . 10.1007/bf02124929. 177801164 .
- (Georg Cantor . Beiträge zur Begründung der transfiniten Mengenlehre (2) . . 49 . 2 . 207–246 . 1897. 10.1007/bf01444205 . 121665994 .)
- Ernst Schröder . Über G. Cantorsche Sätze . . 5 . 81–82 . 1896 .
- Reprinted in:
- Korselt (1911), p.295
- 1904.09193. Cantor-Bernstein implies Excluded Middle. math.LO. Pradic. Cécilia. Brown. Chad E.. 2019.
- Book: Mathematics and Logic in History and in Contemporary Thought . Ettore Carruccio . Transaction Publishers . 2006 . 354 . 978-0-202-30850-0.
- Example 3.