Theories of iterated inductive definitions explained

In set theory and logic, Buchholz's ID hierarchy is a hierarchy of subsystems of first-order arithmetic. The systems/theories

ID\nu

are referred to as "the formal theories of ν-times iterated inductive definitions". IDν extends PA by ν iterated least fixed points of monotone operators.

Definition

Original definition

The formal theory IDω (and IDν in general) is an extension of Peano Arithmetic, formulated in the language LID, by the following axioms:[1]

\forally\forallx

ak{M}
(ak{M}
y,

x)x\in

ak{M}
P
y)

\forally(\forallx(ak{M}y(F,x)F(x))\forallx(x\in

ak{M}
P
y

F(x)))

for every LID-formula F(x)

\forally\forallx0\forall

ak{M}
x
<y

x0x1\leftrightarrowx0<y\landx1\in

ak{M}
P
x0

)

The theory IDν with ν ≠ ω is defined as:

\forally\forallx

ak{M}
(Z
y,

x)x\in

ak{M}
P
y)

\forallx(ak{M}u(F,x)F(x))\forallx

ak{M}
(P
ux

F(x))

for every LID-formula F(x) and each u < ν

\forally\forallx0\forall

ak{M}
x
<y

x0x1\leftrightarrowx0<y\landx1\in

ak{M}
P
x0

)

Explanation / alternate definition

ID1

A set

I\subseteq\N

is called inductively defined if for some monotonic operator

\Gamma:P(N)P(N)

,

LFP(\Gamma)=I

, where

LFP(f)

denotes the least fixed point of

f

. The language of ID1,
L
ID1
, is obtained from that of first-order number theory,

L\N

, by the addition of a set (or predicate) constant IA for every X-positive formula A(X, x) in LN[X] that only contains X (a new set variable) and x (a number variable) as free variables. The term X-positive means that X only occurs positively in A (X is never on the left of an implication). We allow ourselves a bit of set-theoretic notation:

F(x)=\{x\inN\midF(x)\}

s\inF

means

F(s)

F

and

G

,

F\subseteqG

means

\forallxF(x)G(x)

.

Then ID1 contains the axioms of first-order number theory (PA) with the induction scheme extended to the new language as well as these axioms:

1:
(ID
1)

A(IA)\subseteqIA

2:
(ID
1)

A(F)\subseteqFIA\subseteqF

Where

F(x)

ranges over all
L
ID1
formulas.

Note that

1
(ID
1)
expresses that

IA

 is closed under the arithmetically definable set operator

\GammaA(S)=\{x\in\N\mid\N\modelsA(S,x)\}

, while
2
(ID
1)
 expresses that

IA

 is the least such (at least among sets definable in
L
ID1
).

Thus,

IA

 is meant to be the least pre-fixed-point, and hence the least fixed point of the operator

\GammaA

.

IDν

To define the system of ν-times iterated inductive definitions, where ν is an ordinal, let

\prec

 be a primitive recursive well-ordering of order type ν. We use Greek letters to denote elements of the field of

\prec

. The language of IDν,
L
ID\nu
is obtained from

L\N

by the addition of a binary predicate constant JA for every X-positive

L\N[X,Y]

formula

A(X,Y,\mu,x)

that contains at most the shown free variables, where X is again a unary (set) variable, and Y is a fresh binary predicate variable. We write

x\in

\mu
J
A
instead of

JA(\mu,x)

, thinking of x as a distinguished variable in the latter formula.

The system IDν is now obtained from the system of first-order number theory (PA) by expanding the induction scheme to the new language and adding the scheme

(TI\nu):TI(\prec,F)

expressing transfinite induction along

\prec

for an arbitrary
L
ID\nu
 formula

F

 as well as the axioms:
1:
(ID
\nu)

\forall\mu\prec\nu;A\mu(J

\mu
A)

\subseteq

\mu
J
A
2:
(ID
\nu)

\forall\mu\prec\nu;A\mu(F)\subseteqF

\mu
J
A

\subseteqF

where

F(x)

 is an arbitrary
L
ID\nu
 formula. In
1
(ID
\nu)
 and
2
(ID
\nu)
 we used the abbreviation

A\mu(F)

 for the formula

A(F,(λ\gammay;\gamma\prec\mu\landy\in

\gamma
J
A),

\mu,x)

, where

x

 is the distinguished variable. We see that these express that each
\mu
J
A
, for

\mu\prec\nu

, is the least fixed point (among definable sets) for the operator
\mu
\Gamma
A(S)

=\{n\in\N|(\N,

\gamma
(J
A)

\gamma\}

. Note how all the previous sets
\gamma
J
A
, for

\gamma\prec\mu

, are used as parameters.

We then define ID_ = \bigcup _ID_\xi.

Variants

\widehat{ID

}_\nu -

\widehat{ID

}_\nu is a weakened version of

ID\nu

. In the system of

\widehat{ID

}_\nu, a set

I\subseteq\N

is instead called inductively defined if for some monotonic operator

\Gamma:P(N)P(N)

,

I

is a fixed point of

\Gamma

, rather than the least fixed point. This subtle difference makes the system significantly weaker:

PTO(\widehat{ID

}_1) = \psi(\Omega^), while

PTO(ID1)=\psi(\varepsilon\Omega+1)

.

ID\nu\#

is

\widehat{ID

}_\nu weakened even further. In

ID\nu\#

, not only does it use fixed points rather than least fixed points, and has induction only for positive formulas. This once again subtle difference makes the system even weaker:

PTO(ID1\#)=\psi(\Omega\omega)

, while

PTO(\widehat{ID

}_1) = \psi(\Omega^).

W-ID\nu

is the weakest of all variants of

ID\nu

, based on W-types. The amount of weakening compared to regular iterated inductive definitions is identical to removing bar induction given a certain subsystem of second-order arithmetic.

PTO(W-ID1)=\psi0(\Omega x \omega)

, while

PTO(ID1)=\psi(\varepsilon\Omega+1)

.

U(ID\nu)

is an "unfolding" strengthening of

ID\nu

. It is not exactly a first-order arithmetic system, but captures what one can get by predicative reasoning based on ν-times iterated generalized inductive definitions. The amount of increase in strength is identical to the increase from

\varepsilon0

to

\Gamma0

:

PTO(ID1)=\psi(\varepsilon\Omega+1)

, while

PTO(U(ID1))=\psi(\Gamma\Omega+1)

.

Results

1
\Pi
1

-CA+BI

.
0
\Pi
2
-sentence

\forallx\existsy\varphi(x,y)(\varphi\in

0
\Sigma
1)
is provable in IDν, then there exists

p\inN

such that

\foralln\geqp\existsk<

H
n
D
\nu0

(1)\varphi(n,k)

.
k
D
\nu0
\vdash
k

AN

.

Proof-theoretic ordinals

\psi0(\Omega\nu)

.

\psi0(\varepsilon

\Omega\nu+1

)=\psi0(\Omega\nu+1)

.

\widehat{ID}<\omega

is equal to

\Gamma0

.

\widehat{ID}\nu

for

\nu<\omega

is equal to

\varphi(\varphi(\nu,0),0)

.

\widehat{ID}\varphi(\alpha,

is equal to

\varphi(1,0,\varphi(\alpha+1,\beta-1))

.

\widehat{ID}<\varphi(0,

for

\alpha>1

is equal to

\varphi(1,\alpha,0)

.

\widehat{ID}<\nu

for

\nu\geq\varepsilon0

is equal to

\varphi(1,\nu,0)

.

ID\nu\#

is equal to

\varphi(\omega\nu,0)

.

ID<\nu\#

is equal to

\varphi(0,\omega\nu+1)

.

Wrm{-}ID\varphi(\alpha,

is equal to

\psi0(\Omega\varphi(\alpha, x \varphi(\alpha+1,\beta-1))

.

Wrm{-}ID<\varphi(\alpha,

is equal to

\psi0(\varphi(\alpha+1,

\Omega\varphi(\alpha,+1
\beta-1)

)

.

U(ID\nu)

is equal to

\psi0(\varphi(\nu,0,\Omega+1))

.

U(ID<\nu)

is equal to
\Omega+\varphi(\nu,0,\Omega)
\psi
0(\Omega

)

.

KP

,

KP\omega

,

CZF

and
ML1V
.

\psi0(\Omega\omega\varepsilon0)

) is also the proof-theoretic ordinal of

W-KPI

.

KPI

,
1
\Pi
1

-CA+BI

and
1
\Delta
2

-CA+BI

.

\psi0(\Omega

\omega\omega

)

) is also the proof-theoretic ordinal of
1
\Delta
2

-CR

.

\psi0(\Omega

\varepsilon0

)

) is also the proof-theoretic ordinal of
1
\Delta
2

-CA

and
1
\Sigma
2

-AC

.

References

Notes and References

  1. W. Buchholz, "An Independence Result for
    1
    (\Pi
    1rm{-CA})rm{+BI}
    ", Annals of Pure and Applied Logic vol. 33 (1987).