Better Never to Have Been explained

Better Never to Have Been
Author:David Benatar
Language:English
Genre:Philosophy
Publisher:Oxford University Press
Pub Date:2006
Isbn:978-0-199-29642-2
Oclc:427507306
Followed By:The Second Sexism

Better Never to Have Been: The Harm of Coming into Existence is a 2006 book by South African philosopher David Benatar. In the book, Benatar makes a case for antinatalism.

Background

The book was preceded by Benatar's 1997 paper "Why It Is Better Never to Come into Existence",[1] where he expounded on what would eventually become the book's major concepts.[2]

Summary

Better Never to Have Been directly concerns Benatar's antinatalist philosophy: sentient beings are harmed when they are brought into existence, and it is therefore wrong to procreate.[3] He derives this conclusion from two arguments: an asymmetry between good and bad things, such as pleasure and pain, and the view that human beings have an unreliable assessment of life's quality.[4]

Asymmetry between pleasure and pain

Benatar argues that there is what he calls an asymmetry between good and bad things, such as pleasure and pain:

  1. The absence of pain is good, even if that good is not enjoyed by anyone, whereas
  2. The absence of pleasure is not bad unless there is somebody for whom this absence is a deprivation.[5]

His justification for this argument is that the absence of pleasure is only bad when somebody exists to experience that absence; if pleasure is absent and there is no person to be deprived of it, it is not bad.[6]

On the subject of childlessness, he further writes that "the reason why we do not lament our failure to bring somebody into existence is because absent pleasures are not bad."[7]

Critical reception

In his review, philosopher Yujin Nagasawa questioned why Benatar framed Better Never to Have Been as a positive thesis, rather than as a counter-intuitive philosophical puzzle. As a result, Nagasawa felt that he could not recommend the book to everyone.[8] Bioethicist David DeGrazia published a rebuttal to Benatar's arguments in 2010; despite the disagreement with Benatar's position, DeGrazia commended the book, stating: "I conclude with praise for his work and the intellectual virtues it embodies."[9] In 2013, Benatar responded to critics of the book in the paper "Still Better Never to Have Been: A Reply to (More of) My Critics".[10]

In popular culture

The creator of True Detective, Nic Pizzolatto, has cited Better Never to Have Been as an influence on the creation of the character Rust Cohle.[11]

References

  1. Benatar. David. 1997. Why It Is Better Never to Come into Existence. American Philosophical Quarterly. 34. 3. 345–355. 20009904. 0003-0481.
  2. Belshaw. Christopher. 2007-06-09. Review of Better Never to Have Been: The Harm of Coming into Existence. Notre Dame Philosophical Reviews. 1538-1617.
  3. Singh . Asheel . 2018 . The Hypothetical Consent Objection to Anti-Natalism . . en . 21 . 5 . 1135–1150 . 10.1007/s10677-018-9952-0 . 254464712 . 1386-2820 . Anti-natalism is the view that it is (almost) always wrong to bring people (and perhaps all sentient beings) into existence. This view is most famously championed by David Benatar (1997, 2006)..
  4. Smuts . Aaron . 2014 . To Be or Never to Have Been: Anti-Natalism and a Life Worth Living . Ethical Theory and Moral Practice . en . 17 . 4 . 711–729 . 10.1007/s10677-013-9461-0 . 254462083 . 1386-2820 . Benatar presents two independent arguments for anti-natalism. The first argument attempts to show that it is always prudentially bad to be brought into existence. This argument depends on a controversial asymmetry between goods and bads: The absence of pain is good, whereas the absence of pleasure is neither prudentially good nor bad for the non-existent. The prudential asymmetry grounds the anti-natalist moral claim. Accordingly, I will refer to this as the asymmetry argument. The second argument does not depend on the asymmetry. Instead, it defends a wholesale pessimism about the human condition. We can call this the argument from pessimism..
  5. Benatar, David, Better Never to Have Been (2006, 30).
  6. Metz . Thaddeus . 2011 . Are Lives Worth Creating?: Critical Notice of David Benatar, Better Never to Have Been (New York: Oxford University Press, 2006) . . en . 40 . 2 . 233–255 . 10.1080/05568641.2011.591828 . 147119569 . 0556-8641 . Again, Benatar suggests that these emotional reactions are best explained by the asymmetry thesis. In particular, we exhibit negative emotions toward unhappy lives because pain is bad and its absence is good, and we do not exhibit negative emotions toward nonexistent lives that lack happiness because the absence of happiness is not bad when there is no one to be deprived of it..
  7. Benatar, David, Better Never to Have Been (2006, 35).
  8. Nagasawa. Yujin. 2008-07-01. Review: David Benatar: Better Never to Have Been: The Harm of Coming into Existence. Mind. en. 117. 467. 674–677. 10.1093/mind/fzn089. 0026-4423.
  9. DeGrazia. David. 2010-08-01. Is it wrong to impose the harms of human life? A reply to Benatar. Theoretical Medicine and Bioethics. en. 31. 4. 317–331. 10.1007/s11017-010-9152-y. 20625933. 10284785. 1573-1200.
  10. Benatar. David. 2013-06-01. Still Better Never to Have Been: A Reply to (More of) My Critics. The Journal of Ethics. en. 17. 1. 121–151. 10.1007/s10892-012-9133-7. 170682992. 1572-8609.
  11. Web site: Writer Nic Pizzolatto on Thomas Ligotti and the Weird Secrets of 'True Detective'. Calia. Michael. 2014-02-02. WSJ. en-US. 2020-05-31.