Bankruptcy problem explained

A bankruptcy problem, also called a claims problem,[1] is a problem of distributing a homogeneous divisible good (such as money) among people with different claims. The focus is on the case where the amount is insufficient to satisfy all the claims.

The canonical application is a bankrupt firm that is to be liquidated. The firm owes different amounts of money to different creditors, but the total worth of the company's assets is smaller than its total debt. The problem is how to divide the scarce existing money among the creditors.

Another application would be the division of an estate amongst several heirs, particularly when the estate cannot meet all the deceased's commitments.

A third application is tax assessment. One can consider the claimants as taxpayers, the claims as the incomes, and the endowment as the total after-tax income. Determining the allocation of total after-tax income is equivalent to determining the allocation of tax payments.

Definitions

The amount available to divide is denoted by

E

(=Estate or Endowment). There are n claimants. Each claimant i has a claim denoted by

ci

.

It is assumed that

n
\sum
i=1

ci\geqE

, that is, the total claims are (weakly) larger than the estate.

A division rule is a function that maps a problem instance

(c1,\ldots,cn,E)

to a vector

(x1,\ldots,xn)

such that
n
\sum
i=1

xi=E

and

0\leqxi\leqci

for all i. That is: each claimant receives at most its claim, and the sum of allocations is exactly the estate E.

Generalizations

There are generalized variants in which the total claims might be smaller than the estate. In these generalized variants,

n
\sum
i=1

ci\geqE

is not assumed and

0\leqxi\leqci

is not required.

Another generalization, inspired by realistic bankruptcy problems, is to add an exogeneous priority ordering among the claimants, that may be different even for claimants with identical claims. This problem is called a claims problem with priorities. Another variant is called a claims problem with weights.

Rules

There are various rules for solving bankruptcy problems in practice.[2]

rci

, where r is a constant chosen such that
n
\sum
i=1

rci=E

. We denote the outcome of the proportional rule by

PROP(c1,\ldots,cn;E)

.

PROP(c1',\ldots,cn',E)

, where

c'i:=min(ci,E)

.

mi:=max(0,E-\sumjcj)

. Note that
n
\sum
i=1

ci\geqE

implies

mi\leqci

. Then, it revises the claim of agent i to

c'i:=ci-mi

, and the estate to

E':=E-\sumimi

. Note that

E'\geq0

. Finally, it activates the truncated-claims proportional rule, that is, it returns

TPROP(c1,\ldots,cn,E')=PROP(c1'',\ldots,cn'',E')

, where

c''i:=min(c'i,E')

. With two claimants, the revised claims are always equal, so the remainder is divided equally. With three or more claimants, the revised claims may be different.

min(ci,r)

, where r is a constant chosen such that
n
\sum
i=1

min(ci,r)=E

. We denote the outcome of this rule by

CEA(c1,\ldots,cn;E)

. In the context of taxation, it is known as leveling tax.

max(0,ci-r)

, where r is chosen such that
n
\sum
i=1

max(0,ci-r)=E

. This rule was discussed by Maimonides.[4] In the taxation context, it is known as poll tax.

2E<

n
\sum
i=1

ci

then

CG(c1,\ldots,cn;E)=CEA(c1/2,\ldots,cn/2;E)

; Otherwise,

CG(c1,\ldots,cn;E)=c/2+CEL(c1/2,\ldots,cn/2;E-\sumj(cj/2))

.

CEA(c1/2,\ldots,cn/2;E)

; Otherwise, it gives each agent half its claim and then applies CEA on the remainder, that is, it returns

(c1/2,\ldots,cn/2)+CEA(c1/2,\ldots,cn/2;

n
E-\sum
j=1

cj/2)

.

min(ci/2,r)

. Otherwise, it gives each agent i

max(ci/2,min(ci,r))

, In both cases, r is a constant chosen such that the sum of allocations equals E.

RA(c1,\ldots,cn;E)=

1
n!

\sum\pimin(ci,max(0,E-\sum\pi(j)<\pi(i)cj))

.

Bankruptcy rules and cooperative games

Bargaining games

It is possible to associate each bankruptcy problem with a cooperative bargaining problem, and use a bargaining rule to solve the bankruptcy problem. Then:

Coalitional games

It is possible to associate each bankruptcy problem with a cooperative game in which the value of each coalition is its minimal right - the amount that this coalition can ensure itself if all other claimants get their full claim (that is, the amount this coalition can get without going to court). Formally, the value of each subset S of claimants is

v(S):=max\left(0,~E-\sumj\not\incj\right)

. The resulting game is convex, so its core is non-empty. One can use a solution concept for cooperative games, to solve the corresponding bankruptcy problem. Every division rule that depends only on the truncated claims corresponds to a cooperative-game solution. In particular:

An alternative way to associate a claims problem with a cooperative game[10] is its maximal right - the amount that this coalition can ensure itself if all other claimants drop their claims:

v(S):=min\left(E,\sumj\incj\right)

.

Properties of division rules

In most settings, division rules are often required to satisfy the following basic properties:

n
\sum
i=1

xi\leqE

.
n
\sum
i=1

xi=E

.

\foralli:xi\geq0

.

\foralli:xi\leqci

.

\foralli:xi\geqmi,wheremi:=max(0,E-\sumjcj)

.

ci=cj\impliesxi=xj

. In generalized problems of claims with priorities, equal treatment of equals is required to hold for agents in each priority class, but not for agents in different priority classes.

stronger than ETE: if we permute the vector of claims, then the vector of allocations is permuted accordingly.

ci\geqcj\implies(xi\geqxjandci-xi\geqcj-xj)

.

See also

References

Notes and References

  1. Thomson. William. 2003-07-01. Axiomatic and game-theoretic analysis of bankruptcy and taxation problems: a survey. Mathematical Social Sciences. en. 45. 3. 249–297. 10.1016/S0165-4896(02)00070-7. 0165-4896.
  2. Equal Awards vs. Equal Losses in Bankruptcy Problems. SSRN. Alcalde. José. 2017-02-17. Peris. Josep E.. 10.2139/ssrn.2919582 . 2919582 . 158036131 .
  3. Curiel. I. J.. Maschler. M.. Tijs. S. H.. 1987-09-01. Bankruptcy games. Zeitschrift für Operations Research. en. 31. 5. A143–A159. 10.1007/BF02109593. 206811949 . 1432-5217.
  4. Aumann. Robert J. Maschler. Michael. 1985-08-01. Game theoretic analysis of a bankruptcy problem from the Talmud. Journal of Economic Theory. en. 36. 2. 195–213. 10.1016/0022-0531(85)90102-4. 0022-0531.
  5. Book: Piniles, Zvi Menahem. Darkah Shel Torah (Hebrew). Forester. 1863. Wien.
  6. Chun. Youngsub. Schummer. James. Thomson. William. 1998. Constrained Egalitarianism: A New Solution for Claims Problems.
  7. O'Neill. Barry. 1982-06-01. A problem of rights arbitration from the Talmud. Mathematical Social Sciences. en. 2. 4. 345–371. 10.1016/0165-4896(82)90029-4. 0165-4896. 10419/220805. free.
  8. Dagan. Nir. Volij. Oscar. 1993-11-01. The bankruptcy problem: a cooperative bargaining approach. Mathematical Social Sciences. en. 26. 3. 287–297. 10.1016/0165-4896(93)90024-D. 0165-4896.
  9. Dutta. Bhaskar. Ray. Debraj. 1989. A Concept of Egalitarianism Under Participation Constraints. Econometrica. 57. 3. 615–635. 10.2307/1911055. 1911055 . 0012-9682.
  10. Driessen. Theo. 1995. An alternative game theoretic analysis of a bankruptcy problem from the Talmud: the case of the greedy bankruptcy game. English.