Argumentation framework explained

See also: Argumentation theory.

In artificial intelligence and related fields, an argumentation framework is a way to deal with contentious information and draw conclusions from it using formalized arguments.

In an abstract argumentation framework,[1] entry-level information is a set of abstract arguments that, for instance, represent data or a proposition. Conflicts between arguments are represented by a binary relation on the set of arguments. In concrete terms, you represent an argumentation framework with a directed graph such that the nodes are the arguments, and the arrows represent the attack relation.There exist some extensions of the Dung's framework, like the logic-based argumentation frameworks[2] or the value-based argumentation frameworks.[3]

Abstract argumentation frameworks

Formal framework

Abstract argumentation frameworks, also called argumentation frameworks à la Dung, are defined formally as a pair:

A

A

, called attack relation, denoted

R

For instance, the argumentation system

S=\langleA,R\rangle

with

A=\{a,b,c,d\}

and

R=\{(a,b),(b,c),(d,c)\}

contains four arguments (

a,b,c

and

d

) and three attacks (

a

attacks

b

,

b

attacks

c

and

d

attacks

c

).

Dung defines some notions :

a\inA

is acceptable with respect to

E\subseteqA

if and only if

E

defends

a

, that is

\forallb\inA

such that

(b,a)\inR,\existsc\inE

such that

(c,b)\inR

,

E

is conflict-free if there is no attack between its arguments, formally :

\foralla,b\inE,(a,b)\not\inR

,

E

is admissible if and only if it is conflict-free and all its arguments are acceptable with respect to

E

.

Different semantics of acceptance

Extensions

To decide if an argument can be accepted or not, or if several arguments can be accepted together, Dung defines several semantics of acceptance that allows, given an argumentation system, sets of arguments (called extensions) to be computed. For instance, given

S=\langleA,R\rangle

,

E

is a complete extension of

S

only if it is an admissible set and every acceptable argument with respect to

E

belongs to

E

,

E

is a preferred extension of

S

only if it is a maximal element (with respect to the set-theoretical inclusion) among the admissible sets with respect to

S

,

E

is a stable extension of

S

only if it is a conflict-free set that attacks every argument that does not belong in

E

(formally,

\foralla\inA\backslashE,\existsb\inE

such that

(b,a)\inR

,

E

is the (unique) grounded extension of

S

only if it is the smallest element (with respect to set inclusion) among the complete extensions of

S

.There exists some inclusions between the sets of extensions built with these semantics :

a0,a1,...,an,...

such that

\foralli>0,(ai+1,ai)\inR

), all these semantics coincide—only one extension is grounded, stable, preferred, and complete.

Some other semantics have been defined.[4]

One introduce the notation

Ext\sigma(S)

to note the set of

\sigma

-extensions of the system

S

.

In the case of the system

S

in the figure above,

Ext\sigma(S)=\{\{a,d\}\}

for every Dung's semantic—the system is well-founded. That explains why the semantics coincide, and the accepted arguments are:

a

and

d

.

Labellings

Labellings are a more expressive way than extensions to express the acceptance of the arguments. Concretely, a labelling is a mapping that associates every argument with a label in (the argument is accepted), out (the argument is rejected), or undec (the argument is undefined—not accepted or refused).One can also note a labelling as a set of pairs

(argument,label)

.

Such a mapping does not make sense without additional constraint. The notion of reinstatement labelling guarantees the sense of the mapping.

L

is a reinstatement labelling on the system

S=\langleA,R\rangle

if and only if :

\foralla\inA,L(a)=in

if and only if

\forallb\inA

such that

(b,a)\inR,L(b)=out

\foralla\inA,L(a)=out

if and only if

\existsb\inA

such that

(b,a)\inR

and

L(b)=in

\foralla\inA,L(a)=undec

if and only if

L(a)in

and

L(a)out

One can convert every extension into a reinstatement labelling: the arguments of the extension are in, those attacked by an argument of the extension are out, and the others are undec. Conversely, one can build an extension from a reinstatement labelling just by keeping the arguments in. Indeed, Caminada[5] proved that the reinstatement labellings and the complete extensions can be mapped in a bijective way. Moreover, the other Datung's semantics can be associated to some particular sets of reinstatement labellings.

Reinstatement labellings distinguish arguments not accepted because they are attacked by accepted arguments from undefined arguments—that is, those that are not defended cannot defend themselves. An argument is undec if it is attacked by at least another undec. If it is attacked only by arguments out, it must be in, and if it is attacked some argument in, then it is out.

The unique reinstatement labelling that corresponds to the system

S

above is

L=\{(a,in),(b,out),(c,out),(d,in)\}

.

Inference from an argumentation system

In the general case when several extensions are computed for a given semantic

\sigma

, the agent that reasons from the system can use several mechanisms to infer information:[6]

\sigma

-extensions—in which case, the agent risks accepting some arguments that are not acceptable together (

a

attacks

b

, and

a

and

b

each belongs to an extension)

\sigma

-extension. In this case, the agent risks deducing too little information (if the intersection of the extensions is empty or has a very small cardinal).

For these two methods to infer information, one can identify the set of accepted arguments, respectively

Cr\sigma(S)

the set of the arguments credulously accepted under the semantic

\sigma

, and

Sc\sigma(S)

the set of arguments accepted skeptically under the semantic

\sigma

(the

\sigma

can be missed if there is no possible ambiguity about the semantic).

Of course, when there is only one extension (for instance, when the system is well-founded), this problem is very simple: the agent accepts arguments of the unique extension and rejects others.

The same reasoning can be done with labellings that correspond to the chosen semantic : an argument can be accepted if it is in for each labelling and refused if it is out for each labelling, the others being in an undecided state (the status of the arguments can remind the epistemic states of a belief in the AGM framework for dynamic of beliefs[7]).

Equivalence between argumentation frameworks

There exists several criteria of equivalence between argumentation frameworks. Most of those criteria concern the sets of extensions or the set of accepted arguments.Formally, given a semantic

\sigma

:
EQ1
: two argumentation frameworks are equivalent if they have the same set of

\sigma

-extensions, that is

S1\equiv1S2\LeftrightarrowExt\sigma(S1)=Ext\sigma(S2)

;
EQ2
: two argumentation frameworks are equivalent if they accept skeptically the same arguments, that is

S1\equiv2S2\LeftrightarrowSc\sigma(S1)=Sc\sigma(S2)

;
EQ2
: two argumentation frameworks are equivalent if they accept credulously the same arguments, that is

S1\equiv3S2\LeftrightarrowCr\sigma(S1)=Cr\sigma(S2)

.

The strong equivalence[8] says that two systems

S1

and

S2

are equivalent if and only if for all other system

S3

, the union of

S1

with

S3

is equivalent (for a given criterion) with the union of

S2

and

S3

.[9]

Other kinds

The abstract framework of Dung has been instantiated to several particular cases.

Logic-based argumentation frameworks

In the case of logic-based argumentation frameworks, an argument is not an abstract entity, but a pair, where the first part is a minimal consistent set of formulae enough to prove the formula for the second part of the argument.Formally, an argument is a pair

(\Phi,\alpha)

such that

\Phi\nvdash\bot

\Phi\vdash\alpha

\Phi

is a minimal set of

\Delta

satisfying

\alpha

where

\Delta

is a set of formulae used by the agent to reason.

One calls

\alpha

a consequence of

\Phi

, and

\Phi

a support of

\alpha

.

In this case, the attack relation is not given in an explicit way, as a subset of the Cartesian product

A x A

, but as a property that indicates if an argument attacks another. For instance,

(\Psi,\beta)

attacks

(\Phi,\alpha)

if and only if

\beta\vdash\neg(\phi1\wedge...\wedge\phin)

for

\{\phi1,...,\phin\}\subseteq\Phi

(\Psi,\beta)

attacks

(\Phi,\alpha)

if and only if

\beta=\neg(\phi1\wedge...\wedge\phin)

for

\{\phi1,...,\phin\}\subseteq\Phi

(\Psi,\beta)

attacks

(\Phi,\alpha)

if and only if

\beta\Leftrightarrow\neg\alpha

is a tautology

Given a particular attack relation, one can build a graph and reason in a similar way to the abstract argumentation frameworks (use of semantics to build extension, skeptical or credulous inference), the difference is that the information inferred from a logic based argumentation framework is a set of formulae (the consequences of the accepted arguments).

Value-based argumentation frameworks

The value-based argumentation frameworks come from the idea that during an exchange of arguments, some can be stronger than others with respect to a certain value they advance, and so the success of an attack between arguments depends on the difference of these values.

Formally, a value-based argumentation framework is a tuple

VAF=\langleA,R,V,it{val},it{valprefs}\rangle

with

A

and

R

similar to the standard framework (a set of arguments and a binary relation on this set),

V

is a non empty set of values,

it{val}

is a mapping that associates each element from

A

to an element from

V

, and

it{valprefs}

is a preference relation (transitive, irreflexive and asymmetric) on

V x V

.

In this framework, an argument

a

defeats another argument

b

if and only if

a

attacks

b

in the "standard" meaning:

(a,b)\inR

;

(it{val}(b),val(a))\not\init{valprefs}

, that is the value advanced by

b

is not preferred to the one advanced by

a

.One remarks that an attack succeeds if both arguments are associated to the same value, or if there is no preference between their respective values.

Assumption-based argumentation frameworks

In assumption-based argumentation (ABA) frameworks, arguments are defined as a set of rules and attacks are defined in terms of assumptions and contraries.

Formally, an assumption-based argumentation framework is a tuple

\langlel{L},l{R},l{A},\overline{visiblespace}\rangle

,[10] [11] [12] where

\langlel{L},l{R}\rangle

is a deductive system, where

l{L}

is the language and

l{R}

is the set of inference rules in the form of

s0\leftarrows1,...c,sm

, for

m>0

and

s0,s1,...c,sm\inl{L}

;

l{A}

, where

l{A}\subseteql{L}

is a non-empty set, named the assumptions;

\overline{visiblespace}

is a total mapping from

l{A}

to

l{L}

, where

\overline{a}

is defined as the contrary of

a

.As a consequence of defining an ABA, an argument can be represented in a tree-form. Formally, given a deductive system

\langlel{L},l{R}\rangle

and set of assumptions

l{A}\subseteql{L}

, an argument for claim c\in supported by

S\subseteql{A}

, is a tree with nodes labelled by sentences in

l{L}

or by symbol

\tau

, such that:

c

N

,

N

is a leaf node, then

N

is labelled by either an assumption or by

\tau

N

is not a leaf node, then there is an inference rule

lN\leftarrows1,...,sm

,

(m\geq0)

, where

lN

is the label of

N

and

m=0

, then the rule shall be

lN\leftarrow\tau

(i.e. child of

N

is

\tau

)

N

has

m

children, labelled by

s1,...,sm

S

is the set of all assumptions labeling the leave nodesAn argument with claim

c

supported by a set of assumption

S

can also be denoted as

S\vdashc

See also

Notes

  1. See Dung (1995)
  2. See Besnard and Hunter (2001)
  3. see Bench-Capon (2002)
  4. For instance,
    • Ideal : see Dung, Mancarella and Toni (2006)
    • Eager : see Caminada (2007)
  5. see Caminada (2006)
  6. see Touretzky et al.
  7. see Gärdenfors (1988)
  8. see Oikarinen and Woltran (2001)
  9. the union of two systems represents here the system built from the union of the sets of arguments and the union of the attack relations
  10. Book: Argumentation in Artificial Intelligence. Dung. Phan Minh. Kowalski. Robert A.. Toni. Francesca. Francesca Toni . Assumption-Based Argumentation . 2009-01-01. Springer US. 978-0-387-98196-3. Simari. Guillermo. 199–218. en. 10.1007/978-0-387-98197-0_10. Rahwan. Iyad. 10.1.1.188.2433.
  11. Bondarenko. A.. Dung. P. M.. Kowalski. R. A.. Toni. F.. Francesca Toni . 1997-06-01. An abstract, argumentation-theoretic approach to default reasoning. Artificial Intelligence. 93. 1. 63–101. 10.1016/S0004-3702(97)00015-5.
  12. Toni. Francesca. Francesca Toni . 2014-01-02. A tutorial on assumption-based argumentation. Argument & Computation. 5. 1. 89–117. 10.1080/19462166.2013.869878. 1946-2166. free.

References