Alpha recursion theory explained
In recursion theory, α recursion theory is a generalisation of recursion theory to subsets of admissible ordinals
. An admissible set is closed under
functions, where
denotes a rank of Godel's
constructible hierarchy.
is an admissible ordinal if
is a model of
Kripke–Platek set theory. In what follows
is considered to be fixed.
Definitions
The objects of study in
recursion are subsets of
. These sets are said to have some properties:
is said to be
-recursively-enumerable if it is
definable over
, possibly with parameters from
in the definition.
[1]
-recursive
if both A and
(its relative complement in
) are
-recursively-enumerable. It's of note that
-recursive sets are members of
by definition of
.
are called
-finite and play a similar role to the finite numbers in classical recursion theory.
-arithmetic
. [2] There are also some similar definitions for functions mapping
to
:
[3]
to
is
-recursively-enumerable, or
-partial recursive,
[4] iff its graph is
-definable on
.
to
is
-recursive iff its graph is
-definable on
. Like in the case of classical recursion theory, any
total
-recursively-enumerable function
is
-recursive.
- Additionally, a partial function from
to
is
-arithmetical iff there exists some
such that the function's graph is
-definable on
.
Additional connections between recursion theory and α recursion theory can be drawn, although explicit definitions may not have yet been written to formalize them:
-definable in
play a role similar to those of the
primitive recursive functions.
We say R is a reduction procedure if it is
recursively enumerable and every member of R is of the form
where
H,
J,
K are all α-finite.
A is said to be α-recursive in B if there exist
reduction procedures such that:
K\subseteqA\leftrightarrow\existsH:\existsJ:[\langleH,J,K\rangle\inR0\wedgeH\subseteqB\wedgeJ\subseteq\alpha/B],
K\subseteq\alpha/A\leftrightarrow\existsH:\existsJ:[\langleH,J,K\rangle\inR1\wedgeH\subseteqB\wedgeJ\subseteq\alpha/B].
If A is recursive in B this is written
. By this definition
A is recursive in
(the
empty set) if and only if
A is recursive. However A being recursive in B is not equivalent to A being
.
We say A is regular if
\forall\beta\in\alpha:A\cap\beta\inL\alpha
or in other words if every initial portion of
A is α-finite.
Work in α recursion
Shore's splitting theorem: Let A be
recursively enumerable and regular. There exist
recursively enumerable
such that
A=B0\cupB1\wedgeB0\capB1=\varnothing\wedgeA\not\le\alphaBi(i<2).
Shore's density theorem: Let A, C be α-regular recursively enumerable sets such that
then there exists a regular α-recursively enumerable set
B such that
\scriptstyleA<\alphaB<\alphaC
.
Barwise has proved that the sets
-definable on
are exactly the sets
-definable on
, where
denotes the next admissible ordinal above
, and
is from the
Levy hierarchy.
[5] There is a generalization of limit computability to partial
functions.
[6] A computational interpretation of
-recursion exists, using "
-Turing machines" with a two-symbol tape of length
, that at limit computation steps take the limit inferior of cell contents, state, and head position. For admissible
, a set
is
-recursive iff it is computable by an
-Turing machine, and
is
-recursively-enumerable iff
is the range of a function computable by an
-Turing machine.
[7] A problem in α-recursion theory which is open (as of 2019) is the embedding conjecture for admissible ordinals, which is whether for all admissible
, the automorphisms of the
-enumeration degrees embed into the automorphisms of the
-enumeration degrees.
[8] Relationship to analysis
Some results in
-recursion can be translated into similar results about
second-order arithmetic. This is because of the relationship
has with the ramified analytic hierarchy, an analog of
for the language of second-order arithmetic, that consists of sets of integers.
[9] In fact, when dealing with first-order logic only, the correspondence can be close enough that for some results on
, the arithmetical and Levy hierarchies can become interchangeable. For example, a set of natural numbers is definable by a
formula iff it's
-definable on
, where
is a level of the Levy hierarchy.
[10] More generally, definability of a subset of ω over HF with a
formula coincides with its arithmetical definability using a
formula.
[11] References
- Gerald Sacks, Higher recursion theory, Springer Verlag, 1990 https://projecteuclid.org/euclid.pl/1235422631
- Robert Soare, Recursively Enumerable Sets and Degrees, Springer Verlag, 1987 https://projecteuclid.org/euclid.bams/1183541465
- Keith J. Devlin, An introduction to the fine structure of the constructible hierarchy (p.38), North-Holland Publishing, 1974
- J. Barwise, Admissible Sets and Structures. 1975
Inline references
- P. Koepke, B. Seyfferth, Ordinal machines and admissible recursion theory (preprint) (2009, p.315). Accessed October 12, 2021
- R. Gostanian, The Next Admissible Ordinal, Annals of Mathematical Logic 17 (1979). Accessed 1 January 2023.
- Srebrny, Marian, Relatively constructible transitive models (1975, p.165). Accessed 21 October 2021.
- W. Richter, P. Aczel, "Inductive Definitions and Reflecting Properties of Admissible Ordinals" (1974), p.30. Accessed 7 February 2023.
- T. Arai, Proof theory for theories of ordinals - I: recursively Mahlo ordinals (1998). p.2
- S. G. Simpson, "Degree Theory on Admissible Ordinals", pp.170--171. Appearing in J. Fenstad, P. Hinman, Generalized Recursion Theory: Proceedings of the 1972 Oslo Symposium (1974), ISBN 0 7204 22760.
- P. Koepke, B. Seyfferth, "Ordinal machines and admissible recursion theory". Annals of Pure and Applied Logic vol. 160 (2009), pp.310--318.
- D. Natingga, Embedding Theorem for the automorphism group of the α-enumeration degrees (p.155), PhD thesis, 2019.
- P. D. Welch, The Ramified Analytical Hierarchy using Extended Logics (2018, p.4). Accessed 8 August 2021.
- G. E. Sacks, Higher Recursion Theory (p.152). "Perspectives in Logic", Association for Symbolic Logic.
- P. Odifreddi, Classical Recursion Theory (1989), theorem IV.3.22.