Equivalence relation explained

In mathematics, an equivalence relation is a binary relation that is reflexive, symmetric and transitive. The equipollence relation between line segments in geometry is a common example of an equivalence relation. A simpler example is equality. Any number

a

is equal to itself (reflexive). If

a=b

, then

b=a

(symmetric). If

a=b

and

b=c

, then

a=c

(transitive).

Each equivalence relation provides a partition of the underlying set into disjoint equivalence classes. Two elements of the given set are equivalent to each other if and only if they belong to the same equivalence class.

Notation

Various notations are used in the literature to denote that two elements

a

and

b

of a set are equivalent with respect to an equivalence relation

R;

the most common are "

a\simb

" and "", which are used when

R

is implicit, and variations of "

a\simRb

", "", or "

{aRb}

" to specify

R

explicitly. Non-equivalence may be written "" or "

a\not\equivb

".

Definition

\sim

on a set

X

is said to be an equivalence relation, if and only if it is reflexive, symmetric and transitive. That is, for all

a,b,

and

c

in

X:

a\sima

(reflexivity).

a\simb

if and only if

b\sima

(symmetry).

a\simb

and

b\simc

then

a\simc

(transitivity).

X

together with the relation

\sim

is called a setoid. The equivalence class of

a

under

\sim,

denoted

[a],

is defined as

[a]=\{x\inX:x\sima\}.

[1] [2]

Alternative definition using relational algebra

In relational algebra, if

R\subseteqX x Y

and

S\subseteqY x Z

are relations, then the composite relation

SR\subseteqX x Z

is defined so that

xSRz

if and only if there is a

y\inY

such that

xRy

and

ySz

.[3] This definition is a generalisation of the definition of functional composition. The defining properties of an equivalence relation

R

on a set

X

can then be reformulated as follows:

\operatorname{id}\subseteqR

. (reflexivity). (Here,

\operatorname{id}

denotes the identity function on

X

.)

R=R-1

(symmetry).

RR\subseteqR

(transitivity).[4]

Examples

Simple example

On the set

X=\{a,b,c\}

, the relation

R=\{(a,a),(b,b),(c,c),(b,c),(c,b)\}

is an equivalence relation. The following sets are equivalence classes of this relation:[a] = \, ~~~~ [b] = [c] = \.

The set of all equivalence classes for

R

is

\{\{a\},\{b,c\}\}.

This set is a partition of the set

X

with respect to

R

.

Equivalence relations

The following relations are all equivalence relations:

\tfrac{1}{2}

is equal to

\tfrac{4}{8}.

n

, "is congruent to, modulo

n

" on the integers.

f:X\toY

, "has the same image under

f

as" on the elements of

f

's domain

X

. For example,

0

and

\pi

have the same image under

\sin

, viz.

0

.

Relations that are not equivalences

Connections to other relations

a,

there exists some

bsuchthata\simb.

[5] Therefore, an equivalence relation may be alternatively defined as a symmetric, transitive, and total relation.

X

is also the underlying set for an algebraic structure, and which respects the additional structure. In general, congruence relations play the role of kernels of homomorphisms, and the quotient of a structure by a congruence relation can be formed. In many important cases, congruence relations have an alternative representation as substructures of the structure on which they are defined (e.g., the congruence relations on groups correspond to the normal subgroups).

Well-definedness under an equivalence relation

If

\sim

is an equivalence relation on

X,

and

P(x)

is a property of elements of

X,

such that whenever

x\simy,

P(x)

is true if

P(y)

is true, then the property

P

is said to be well-defined or a under the relation

\sim.

A frequent particular case occurs when

f

is a function from

X

to another set

Y;

if

x1\simx2

implies

f\left(x1\right)=f\left(x2\right)

then

f

is said to be a for

\sim,

a

\sim,

or simply

\sim.

This occurs, e.g. in the character theory of finite groups. The latter case with the function

f

can be expressed by a commutative triangle. See also invariant. Some authors use "compatible with

\sim

" or just "respects

\sim

" instead of "invariant under

\sim

".

More generally, a function may map equivalent arguments (under an equivalence relation

\simA

) to equivalent values (under an equivalence relation

\simB

). Such a function is known as a morphism from

\simA

to

\simB.

Related important definitions

Let

a,b\inX

, and

\sim

be an equivalence relation. Some key definitions and terminology follow:

Equivalence class

See main article: Equivalence class.

A subset

Y

of

X

such that

a\simb

holds for all

a

and

b

in

Y

, and never for

a

in

Y

and

b

outside

Y

, is called an equivalence class of

X

by

\sim

. Let

[a]:=\{x\inX:a\simx\}

denote the equivalence class to which

a

belongs. All elements of

X

equivalent to each other are also elements of the same equivalence class.

Quotient set

The set of all equivalence classes of

X

by

\sim,

denoted

X/d{\sim}:=\{[x]:x\inX\},

is the quotient set of

X

by

\sim.

If

X

is a topological space, there is a natural way of transforming

X/\sim

into a topological space; see Quotient space for the details.

Projection

See main article: Projection (relational algebra).

The projection of

\sim

is the function

\pi:X\toX/d{\sim}

defined by

\pi(x)=[x]

which maps elements of

X

into their respective equivalence classes by

\sim.

Theorem on projections:[6] Let the function

f:X\toB

be such that if

a\simb

then

f(a)=f(b).

Then there is a unique function

g:X/\sim\toB

such that

f=g\pi.

If

f

is a surjection and

a\simbifandonlyiff(a)=f(b),

then

g

is a bijection.

Equivalence kernel

The equivalence kernel of a function

f

is the equivalence relation ~ defined by

x\simyifandonlyiff(x)=f(y).

The equivalence kernel of an injection is the identity relation.

Partition

See main article: Partition of a set. A partition of X is a set P of nonempty subsets of X, such that every element of X is an element of a single element of P. Each element of P is a cell of the partition. Moreover, the elements of P are pairwise disjoint and their union is X.

Counting partitions

Let X be a finite set with n elements. Since every equivalence relation over X corresponds to a partition of X, and vice versa, the number of equivalence relations on X equals the number of distinct partitions of X, which is the nth Bell number Bn:

B_n = \frac \sum_^\infty \frac \quad (Dobinski's formula).

Fundamental theorem of equivalence relations

A key result links equivalence relations and partitions:[7] [8] [9]

In both cases, the cells of the partition of X are the equivalence classes of X by ~. Since each element of X belongs to a unique cell of any partition of X, and since each cell of the partition is identical to an equivalence class of X by ~, each element of X belongs to a unique equivalence class of X by ~. Thus there is a natural bijection between the set of all equivalence relations on X and the set of all partitions of X.

Comparing equivalence relations

If

\sim

and

are two equivalence relations on the same set

S

, and

a\simb

implies

ab

for all

a,b\inS,

then

is said to be a coarser relation than

\sim

, and

\sim

is a finer relation than

. Equivalently,

\sim

is finer than

if every equivalence class of

\sim

is a subset of an equivalence class of

, and thus every equivalence class of

is a union of equivalence classes of

\sim

.

\sim

is finer than

if the partition created by

\sim

is a refinement of the partition created by

.

The equality equivalence relation is the finest equivalence relation on any set, while the universal relation, which relates all pairs of elements, is the coarsest.

The relation "

\sim

is finer than

" on the collection of all equivalence relations on a fixed set is itself a partial order relation, which makes the collection a geometric lattice.[10]

Generating equivalence relations

X,

an equivalence relation over the set

[X\toX]

of all functions

X\toX

can be obtained as follows. Two functions are deemed equivalent when their respective sets of fixpoints have the same cardinality, corresponding to cycles of length one in a permutation.

\sim

on

X

is the equivalence kernel of its surjective projection

\pi:X\toX/\sim.

[11] Conversely, any surjection between sets determines a partition on its domain, the set of preimages of singletons in the codomain. Thus an equivalence relation over

X,

a partition of

X,

and a projection whose domain is

X,

are three equivalent ways of specifying the same thing.

X x X

) is also an equivalence relation. This yields a convenient way of generating an equivalence relation: given any binary relation R on X, the equivalence relation is the intersection of all equivalence relations containing R (also known as the smallest equivalence relation containing R). Concretely, R generates the equivalence relation

a\simb

if there exists a natural number

n

and elements

x0,\ldots,xn\inX

such that

a=x0

,

b=xn

, and

xi-1l{R}xi

or

xil{R}xi-1

, for

i=1,\ldots,n.

The equivalence relation generated in this manner can be trivial. For instance, the equivalence relation generated by any total order on X has exactly one equivalence class, X itself.

[0,1] x [0,1],

and let ~ be the equivalence relation on X defined by

(a,0)\sim(a,1)

for all

a\in[0,1]

and

(0,b)\sim(1,b)

for all

b\in[0,1],

Then the quotient space

X/\sim

can be naturally identified (homeomorphism) with a torus: take a square piece of paper, bend and glue together the upper and lower edge to form a cylinder, then bend the resulting cylinder so as to glue together its two open ends, resulting in a torus.

Algebraic structure

Much of mathematics is grounded in the study of equivalences, and order relations. Lattice theory captures the mathematical structure of order relations. Even though equivalence relations are as ubiquitous in mathematics as order relations, the algebraic structure of equivalences is not as well known as that of orders. The former structure draws primarily on group theory and, to a lesser extent, on the theory of lattices, categories, and groupoids.

Group theory

Just as order relations are grounded in ordered sets, sets closed under pairwise supremum and infimum, equivalence relations are grounded in partitioned sets, which are sets closed under bijections that preserve partition structure. Since all such bijections map an equivalence class onto itself, such bijections are also known as permutations. Hence permutation groups (also known as transformation groups) and the related notion of orbit shed light on the mathematical structure of equivalence relations.

Let '~' denote an equivalence relation over some nonempty set A, called the universe or underlying set. Let G denote the set of bijective functions over A that preserve the partition structure of A, meaning that for all

x\inA

and

g\inG,g(x)\in[x].

Then the following three connected theorems hold:[12]

In sum, given an equivalence relation ~ over A, there exists a transformation group G over A whose orbits are the equivalence classes of A under ~.

This transformation group characterisation of equivalence relations differs fundamentally from the way lattices characterize order relations. The arguments of the lattice theory operations meet and join are elements of some universe A. Meanwhile, the arguments of the transformation group operations composition and inverse are elements of a set of bijections, AA.

Moving to groups in general, let H be a subgroup of some group G. Let ~ be an equivalence relation on G, such that

a\simbifandonlyifab-1\inH.

The equivalence classes of ~ - also called the orbits of the action of H on G - are the right cosets of H in G. Interchanging a and b yields the left cosets.

Related thinking can be found in Rosen (2008: chpt. 10).

Categories and groupoids

x\simy.

The advantages of regarding an equivalence relation as a special case of a groupoid include:

Lattices

The equivalence relations on any set X, when ordered by set inclusion, form a complete lattice, called Con X by convention. The canonical map ker : X^XCon X, relates the monoid X^X of all functions on X and Con X. ker is surjective but not injective. Less formally, the equivalence relation ker on X, takes each function f : XX to its kernel ker f. Likewise, ker(ker) is an equivalence relation on X^X.

Equivalence relations and mathematical logic

Equivalence relations are a ready source of examples or counterexamples. For example, an equivalence relation with exactly two infinite equivalence classes is an easy example of a theory which is ω-categorical, but not categorical for any larger cardinal number.

An implication of model theory is that the properties defining a relation can be proved independent of each other (and hence necessary parts of the definition) if and only if, for each property, examples can be found of relations not satisfying the given property while satisfying all the other properties. Hence the three defining properties of equivalence relations can be proved mutually independent by the following three examples:

Properties definable in first-order logic that an equivalence relation may or may not possess include:

References

External links

Notes and References

  1. Web site: Weisstein. Eric W.. Equivalence Class. 2020-08-30. mathworld.wolfram.com. en.
  2. Web site: 2017-09-20. 7.3: Equivalence Classes. 2020-08-30. Mathematics LibreTexts. en.
  3. Sometimes the composition

    SR\subseteqX x Z

    is instead written as

    R;S

    , or as

    RS

    ; in both cases,

    R

    is the first relation that is applied. See the article on Composition of relations for more information.
  4. Book: Halmos, Paul Richard . Naive Set Theory . Springer . 1914 . 978-0-387-90104-6 . New York . 41 . English.
  5. If: Given

    a,

    let

    a\simb

    hold using totality, then

    b\sima

    by symmetry, hence

    a\sima

    by transitivity. - Only if: Given

    a,

    choose

    b=a,

    then

    a\simb

    by reflexivity.
  6. [Garrett Birkhoff]
  7. Wallace, D. A. R., 1998. Groups, Rings and Fields. p. 31, Th. 8. Springer-Verlag.
  8. Dummit, D. S., and Foote, R. M., 2004. Abstract Algebra, 3rd ed. p. 3, Prop. 2. John Wiley & Sons.
  9. [Karel Hrbacek]
  10. . Sect. IV.9, Theorem 12, page 95
  11. [Garrett Birkhoff]
  12. Rosen (2008), pp. 243–45. Less clear is §10.3 of Bas van Fraassen, 1989. Laws and Symmetry. Oxford Univ. Press.
  13. Wallace, D. A. R., 1998. Groups, Rings and Fields. Springer-Verlag: 202, Th. 6.
  14. Dummit, D. S., and Foote, R. M., 2004. Abstract Algebra, 3rd ed. John Wiley & Sons: 114, Prop. 2.
  15. Borceux, F. and Janelidze, G., 2001. Galois theories, Cambridge University Press,